Skip to main content

Full text of "The Origin Of Biological Information And The Higher Taxonomic Categories"

See other formats


PROCEEDINGS OF THE BIOLOGICAL SOCIETY OF WASHINGTON 
117(2):2 13-239. 2004. 

The origin of biological information and the 
higher taxonomic categories 



Stephen C. Meyer 

Palm Beach Atlantic University, 901 S. Flagler Dr., West Palm Beach, Florida 33401 
e-mail: stevemeyer@discovery.org 



Introduction 

In a recent volume of the Vienna Series 
in Theoretical Biology (2003), Gerd B. 
Muller and Stuart Newman argue that what 
they call the “origination of organismal 
form” remains an unsolved problem. In 
making this claim, Muller and Newman 
(2003:3-10) distinguish two distinct issues, 
namely, (1) the causes of form generation 
in the individual organism during embryo- 
logical development and (2) the causes re- 
sponsible for the production of novel or- 
ganismal forms in the first place during the 
history of life. To distinguish the latter case 
(phylogeny) from the former (ontogeny), 
Muller and Newman use the term “origi- 
nation” to designate the causal processes by 
which biological form first arose during the 
evolution of life. They insist that “the mo- 
lecular mechanisms that bring about biolog- 
ical form in modem day embryos should 
not be confused” with the causes respon- 
sible for the origin (or “origination”) of 
novel biological forms during the history of 
life (p. 3). They further argue that we know 
more about the causes of ontogenesis, due 
to advances in molecular biology, molecu- 
lar genetics and developmental biology, 
than we do about the causes of phylogen- 
esis — the ultimate origination of new bio- 
logical forms during the remote past. 

In making this claim, Muller and New- 
man are careful to affirm that evolutionary 
biology has succeeded in explaining how 
pre-existing forms diversify under the twin 
influences of natural selection and variation 
of genetic traits. Sophisticated mathemati- 
cally-based models of population genetics 



have proven adequate for mapping and un- 
derstanding quantitative variability and 
populational changes in organisms. Yet 
Muller and Newman insist that population 
genetics, and thus evolutionary biology, has 
not identified a specifically causal expla- 
nation for the origin of true morphological 
novelty during the history of life. Central 
to their concern is what they see as the in- 
adequacy of the variation of genetic traits 
as a source of new form and structure. They 
note, following Darwin himself, that the 
sources of new form and structure must pre- 
cede the action of natural selection (2003: 
3) — that selection must act on what already 
exists. Yet, in their view, the “genocentric- 
ity” and “incrementalism” of the neo-Dar- 
winian mechanism has meant that an ade- 
quate source of new form and structure has 
yet to be identified by theoretical biologists. 
Instead, Muller and Newman see the need 
to identify epigenetic sources of morpho- 
logical innovation during the evolution of 
life. In the meantime, however, they insist 
neo-Darwinism lacks any “theory of the 
generative” (p. 7). 

As it happens, Muller and Newman are 
not alone in this judgment. In the last de- 
cade or so a host of scientific essays and 
books have questioned the efficacy of se- 
lection and mutation as a mechanism for 
generating morphological novelty, as even 
a brief literature survey will establish. 
Thomson (1992:107) expressed doubt that 
large-scale morphological changes could 
accumulate via minor phenotypic changes 
at the population genetic level. Miklos 
(1993:29) argued that neo-Darwinism fails 
to provide a mechanism that can produce 



214 



PROCEEDINGS OF THE BIOLOGICAL SOCIETY OF WASHINGTON 



large-scale innovations in form and com- 
plexity. Gilbert et al. (1996) attempted to 
develop a new theory of evolutionary 
mechanisms to supplement classical neo- 
Darwinism, which, they argued, could not 
adequately explain macroevolution. As they 
put it in a memorable summary of the sit- 
uation: “starting in the 1970s, many biol- 
ogists began questioning its [neo-Darwin- 
ism’s] adequacy in explaining evolution. 
Genetics might be adequate for explaining 
microevolution, but microevolutionary 
changes in gene frequency were not seen as 
able to turn a reptile into a mammal or to 
convert a fish into an amphibian. Microevo- 
lution looks at adaptations that concern the 
survival of the fittest, not the arrival of the 
fittest. As Goodwin (1995) points out, ‘the 
origin of species — Darwin’s problem — re- 
mains unsolved’ ” (p. 361). Though Gilbert 
et al. (1996) attempted to solve the problem 
of the origin of form by proposing a greater 
role for developmental genetics within an 
otherwise neo-Darwinian framework, 1 nu- 
merous recent authors have continued to 
raise questions about the adequacy of that 
framework itself or about the problem of 
the origination of form generally (Webster 
& Goodwin 1996; Shubin & Marshall 
2000; Erwin 2000; Conway Morris 2000, 
2003b; Carrol 2000; Wagner 2001; Becker 
& Lonnig 2001; Stadler et al. 2001; Lonnig 
& Saedler 2002; Wagner & Stadler 2003; 
Valentine 2004:189-194). 

What lies behind this skepticism? Is it 
warranted? Is a new and specifically causal 
theory needed to explain the origination of 
biological form? 

This review will address these questions. 
It will do so by analyzing the problem of 
the origination of organismal form (and the 



1 Specifically, Gilbert et al. (1996) argued that 
changes in morphogenetic fields might produce large- 
scale changes in the developmental programs and, ul- 
timately, body plans of organisms. Yet they offered no 
evidence that such fields — if indeed they exist — can 
be altered to produce advantageous variations in body 
plan, though this is a necessary condition of any suc- 
cessful causal theory of macroevolution. 



corresponding emergence of higher taxa) 
from a particular theoretical standpoint. 
Specifically, it will treat the problem of the 
origination of the higher taxonomic groups 
as a manifestation of a deeper problem, 
namely, the problem of the origin of the 
information (whether genetic or epigenetic) 
that, as it will be argued, is necessary to 
generate morphological novelty. 

In order to perform this analysis, and to 
make it relevant and tractable to systema- 
tists and paleontologists, this paper will ex- 
amine a paradigmatic example of the origin 
of biological form and information during 
the history of life: the Cambrian explosion. 
During the Cambrian, many novel animal 
forms and body plans (representing new 
phyla, sub-phyla and classes) arose in a 
geologically brief period of time. The fol- 
lowing information-based analysis of the 
Cambrian explosion will support the claim 
of recent authors such as Muller and New- 
man that the mechanism of selection and 
genetic mutation does not constitute an ad- 
equate causal explanation of the origination 
of biological form in the higher taxonomic 
groups. It will also suggest the need to ex- 
plore other possible causal factors for the 
origin of form and information during the 
evolution of life and will examine some 
other possibilities that have been proposed. 

The Cambrian Explosion 

The “Cambrian explosion” refers to the 
geologically sudden appearance of many 
new animal body plans about 530 million 
years ago. At this time, at least nineteen, 
and perhaps as many as thirty-five phyla of 
forty total (Meyer et al. 2003), made their 
first appearance on Earth within a narrow 
five- to ten-million-year window of geolog- 
ic time (Bowring et al. 1993, 1998a:l, 
1998b:40; Kerr 1993; Monastersky 1993; 
Aris-Brosou & Yang 2003). Many new sub- 
phyla, between 32 and 48 of 56 total (Mey- 
er et al. 2003), and classes of animals also 
arose at this time with representatives of 
these new higher taxa manifesting signifi- 



VOLUME 1 17, NUMBER 2 



215 



cant morphological innovations. The Cam- 
brian explosion thus marked a major epi- 
sode of morphogenesis in which many new 
and disparate organismal forms arose in a 
geologically brief period of time. 

To say that the fauna of the Cambrian 
period appeared in a geologically sudden 
manner also implies the absence of clear 
transitional intermediate forms connecting 
Cambrian animals with simpler pre-Cam- 
brian forms. And, indeed, in almost all cas- 
es, the Cambrian animals have no clear 
morphological antecedents in earlier Ven- 
dian or Precambrian fauna (Miklos 1993, 
Erwin et al. 1997:132, Steiner & Reitner 
2001, Conway Morris 2003b:510, Valentine 
et al. 2003:519-520). Further, several re- 
cent discoveries and analyses suggest that 
these morphological gaps may not be mere- 
ly an artifact of incomplete sampling of the 
fossil record (Foote 1997, Foote et al. 1999, 
Benton & Ayala 2003, Meyer et al. 2003), 
suggesting that the fossil record is at least 
approximately reliable (Conway Morris 
2003b:505). 

As a result, debate now exists about the 
extent to which this pattern of evidence 
comports with a strictly monophyletic view 
of evolution (Conway Morris 1998a, 2003a, 
2003b:510; Willmer 1990, 2003). Further, 
among those who accept a monophyletic 
view of the history of life, debate exists 
about whether to privilege fossil or molec- 
ular data and analyses. Those who think the 
fossil data provide a more reliable picture of 
the origin of the Metazoan tend to think 
these animals arose relatively quickly — that 
the Cambrian explosion had a “short fuse.” 
(Conway Morris 2003b:505-506, Valentine 
& Jablonski 2003). Some (Wray et al. 1996), 
but not all (Ayala et al. 1998), who think 
that molecular phylogenies establish reliable 
divergence times from pre-Cambrian ances- 
tors think that the Cambrian animals evolved 
over a very long period of time — that the 
Cambrian explosion had a “long fuse.” This 
review will not address these questions of 
historical pattern. Instead, it will analyze 
whether the neo-Darwinian process of mu- 



tation and selection, or other processes of 
evolutionary change, can generate the form 
and information necessary to produce the 
animals that arise in the Cambrian. This 
analysis will, for the most part, 2 therefore, 
not depend upon assumptions of either a 
long or short fuse for the Cambrian explo- 
sion, or upon a monophyletic or polyphyletic 
view of the early history of life. 

Defining Biological Form and Information 

Form, like life itself, is easy to recognize 
but often hard to define precisely. Yet, a rea- 
sonable working definition of form will suf- 
fice for our present purposes. Form can be 
defined as the four-dimensional topological 
relations of anatomical parts. This means that 
one can understand form as a unified arrange- 
ment of body parts or material components 
in a distinct shape or pattern (topology) — one 
that exists in three spatial dimensions and 
which arises in time during ontogeny. 

Insofar as any particular biological form 
constitutes something like a distinct ar- 
rangement of constituent body parts, form 
can be seen as arising from constraints that 
limit the possible arrangements of matter. 
Specifically, organismal form arises (both 
in phylogeny and ontogeny) as possible ar- 
rangements of material parts are con- 
strained to establish a specific or particular 
arrangement with an identifiable three di- 
mensional topography — one that we would 
recognize as a particular protein, cell type, 
organ, body plan or organism. A particular 



2 If one takes the fossil record at face value and 
assumes that the Cambrian explosion took place within 
a relatively narrow 5-1 0 million year window, explain- 
ing the origin of the information necessary to produce 
new proteins, for example, becomes more acute in part 
because mutation rates would not have been sufficient 
to generate the number of changes in the genome nec- 
essary to build the new proteins for more complex 
Cambrian animals (Ohno 1996:8475-8478). This re- 
view will argue that, even if one allows several hun- 
dred million years for the origin of the metazoan, sig- 
nificant probabilistic and other difficulties remain with 
the neo-Darwinian explanation of the origin of form 
and information. 



216 



PROCEEDINGS OF THE BIOLOGICAL SOCIETY OF WASHINGTON 



“form,” therefore, represents a highly spe- 
cific and constrained arrangement of mate- 
rial components (among a much larger set 
of possible arrangements). 

Understanding form in this way suggests 
a connection to the notion of information in 
its most theoretically general sense. When 
Shannon (1948) first developed a mathe- 
matical theory of information he equated 
the amount of information transmitted with 
the amount of uncertainty reduced or elim- 
inated in a series of symbols or characters. 
Information, in Shannon’s theory, is thus 
imparted as some options are excluded and 
others are actualized. The greater the num- 
ber of options excluded, the greater the 
amount of information conveyed. Further, 
constraining a set of possible material ar- 
rangements by whatever process or means 
involves excluding some options and actu- 
alizing others. Thus, to constrain a set of 
possible material states is to generate infor- 
mation in Shannon’s sense. It follows that 
the constraints that produce biological form 
also impart in/brmation. Or conversely, one 
might say that producing organismal form 
by definition requires the generation of in- 
formation. 

In classical Shannon information theory, 
the amount of information in a system is 
also inversely related to the probability of 
the arrangement of constituents in a system 
or the characters along a communication 
channel (Shannon 1948). The more improb- 
able (or complex) the arrangement, the 
more Shannon information, or information- 
carrying capacity, a string or system pos- 
sesses. 

Since the 1960s, mathematical biologists 
have realized that Shannon’s theory could 
be applied to the analysis of DNA and pro- 
teins to measure the information-carrying 
capacity of these macromolecules. Since 
DNA contains the assembly instructions for 
building proteins, the information-process- 
ing system in the cell represents a kind of 
communication channel (Yockey 1992: 
110). Further, DNA conveys information 
via specifically arranged sequences of nu- 



cleotide bases. Since each of the four bases 
has a roughly equal chance of occurring at 
each site along the spine of the DNA mol- 
ecule, biologists can calculate the probabil- 
ity, and thus the information-carrying ca- 
pacity, of any particular sequence n bases 
long. 

The ease with which information theory 
applies to molecular biology has created 
confusion about the type of information that 
DNA and proteins possess. Sequences of 
nucleotide bases in DNA, or amino acids in 
a protein, are highly improbable and thus 
have large information-carrying capacities. 
But, like meaningful sentences or lines of 
computer code, genes and proteins are also 
specified with respect to function. Just as 
the meaning of a sentence depends upon the 
specific arrangement of the letters in a sen- 
tence, so too does the function of a gene 
sequence depend upon the specific arrange- 
ment of the nucleotide bases in a gene. 
Thus, molecular biologists beginning with 
Crick equated information not only with 
complexity but also with “specificity,” 
where “specificity” or “specified” has 
meant “necessary to function” (Crick 
1958:144, 153; Sarkar, 1996:191). 3 Molec- 
ular biologists such as Monod and Crick 
understood biological information — the in- 
formation stored in DNA and proteins — as 
something more than mere complexity (or 
improbability). Their notion of information 
associated both biochemical contingency 
and combinatorial complexity with DNA 
sequences (allowing DNA’s carrying capac- 
ity to be calculated), but it also affirmed 
that sequences of nucleotides and amino ac- 
ids in functioning macromolecules pos- 
sessed a high degree of specificity relative 
to the maintenance of cellular function. 

The ease with which information theory 
applies to molecular biology has also cre- 
ated confusion about the location of infor- 



3 As Crick put it, “information means here the pre- 
cise determination of sequence, either of bases in the 
nucleic acid or on amino acid residues in the protein” 
(Crick 1958:144, 153). 



VOLUME 117, NUMBER 2 



217 



mation in organisms. Perhaps because the 
information carrying capacity of the gene 
could be so easily measured, it has been 
easy to treat DNA, RNA and proteins as the 
sole repositories of biological information. 
Neo-Darwinists in particular have assumed 
that the origination of biological form could 
be explained by recourse to processes of ge- 
netic variation and mutation alone (Levin- 
ton 1988:485). Yet if one understands or- 
ganismal form as resulting from constraints 
on the possible arrangements of matter at 
many levels in the biological hierarchy — 
from genes and proteins to cell types and 
tissues to organs and body plans — then 
clearly biological organisms exhibit many 
levels of information-rich structure. 

Thus, we can pose a question, not only 
about the origin of genetic information, but 
also about the origin of the information nec- 
essary to generate form and structure at lev- 
els higher than that present in individual 
proteins. We must also ask about the origin 
of the “specified complexity,” as opposed 
to mere complexity, that characterizes the 
new genes, proteins, cell types and body 
plans that arose in the Cambrian explosion. 
Dembski (2002) has used the term “com- 
plex specified information” (CSI) as a syn- 
onym for “specified complexity” to help 
distinguish functional biological informa- 
tion from mere Shannon information — that 
is, specified complexity from mere com- 
plexity. This review will use this term as 
well. 

The Cambrian Information Explosion 

The Cambrian explosion represents a re- 
markable jump in the specified complexity 
or “complex specified information” (CSI) 
of the biological world. For over three bil- 
lion years, the biological realm included lit- 
tle more than bacteria and algae (Brocks et 
al. 1999). Then, beginning about 570-565 
million years ago (mya), the first complex 
multicellular organisms appeared in the 
rock strata, including sponges, cnidarians, 
and the peculiar Ediacaran biota (Grotzin- 



ger et al. 1995). Forty million years later, 
the Cambrian explosion occurred (Bowring 
et al. 1993). The emergence of the Edi- 
acaran biota (570 mya), and then to a much 
greater extent the Cambrian explosion (530 
mya), represented steep climbs up the bio- 
logical complexity gradient. 

One way to estimate the amount of new 
CSI that appeared with the Cambrian ani- 
mals is to count the number of new cell 
types that emerged with them (Valentine 
1995:91-93). Studies of modem animals 
suggest that the sponges that appeared in 
the late Precambrian, for example, would 
have required five cell types, whereas the 
more complex animals that appeared in the 
Cambrian (e.g., arthropods) would have re- 
quired fifty or more cell types. Functionally 
more complex animals require more cell 
types to perform their more diverse func- 
tions. New cell types require many new and 
specialized proteins. New proteins, in turn, 
require new genetic information. Thus an 
increase in the number of cell types implies 
(at a minimum) a considerable increase in 
the amount of specified genetic informa- 
tion. Molecular biologists have recently es- 
timated that a minimally complex single- 
celled organism would require between 3 1 8 
and 562 kilobase pairs of DNA to produce 
the proteins necessary to maintain life 
(Koonin 2000). More complex single cells 
might require upward of a million base 
pairs. Yet to build the proteins necessary to 
sustain a complex arthropod such as a tri- 
lobite would require orders of magnitude 
more coding instructions. The genome size 
of a modern arthropod, the fruitfly Dro- 
sophila melanogaster, is approximately 1 80 
million base pairs (Gerhart & Kirschner 
1997:121, Adams et al. 2000). Transitions 
from a single cell to colonies of cells to 
complex animals represent significant (and, 
in principle, measurable) increases in CSI. 

Building a new animal from a single- 
celled organism requires a vast amount of 
new genetic information. It also requires a 
way of arranging gene products — pro- 
teins — into higher levels of organization. 



218 



PROCEEDINGS OF THE BIOLOGICAL SOCIETY OF WASHINGTON 



New proteins are required to service new 
cell types. But new proteins must be orga- 
nized into new systems within the cell; new 
cell types must be organized into new tis- 
sues, organs, and body parts. These, in turn, 
must be organized to form body plans. New 
animals, therefore, embody hierarchically 
organized systems of lower-level parts 
within a functional whole. Such hierarchi- 
cal organization itself represents a type of 
information, since body plans comprise 
both highly improbable and functionally 
specified arrangements of lower-level parts. 
The specified complexity of new body 
plans requires explanation in any account of 
the Cambrian explosion. 

Can neo-Darwinism explain the discon- 
tinuous increase in CSI that appears in the 
Cambrian explosion — either in the form of 
new genetic information or in the form of 
hierarchically organized systems of parts? 
We will now examine the two parts of this 
question. 

Novel Genes and Proteins 

Many scientists and mathematicians have 
questioned the ability of mutation and se- 
lection to generate information in the form 
of novel genes and proteins. Such skepti- 
cism often derives from consideration of 
the extreme improbability (and specificity) 
of functional genes and proteins. 

A typical gene contains over one thousand 
precisely arranged bases. For any specific ar- 
rangement of four nucleotide bases of length 
n, there is a corresponding number of pos- 
sible arrangements of bases, 4". For any pro- 
tein, there are 20" possible arrangements of 
protein-forming amino acids. A gene 999 
bases in length represents one of 4 999 possi- 
ble nucleotide sequences; a protein of 333 
amino acids is one of 20 333 possibilities. 

Since the 1960s, some biologists have 
thought functional proteins to be rare among 
the set of possible amino acid sequences. 
Some have used an analogy with human lan- 
guage to illustrate why this should be the 
case. Denton (1986, 309-31 1), for example. 



has shown that meaningful words and sen- 
tences are extremely rare among the set of 
possible combinations of English letters, es- 
pecially as sequence length grows. (The ra- 
tio of meaningful 12-letter words to 12-letter 
sequences is 1/10 14 ; the ratio of 100-letter 
sentences to possible 100-letter strings is 
1/1 0 100 .) Further, Denton shows that most 
meaningful sentences are highly isolated 
from one another in the space of possible 
combinations, so that random substitutions 
of letters will, after a very few changes, in- 
evitably degrade meaning. Apart from a few 
closely clustered sentences accessible by 
random substitution, the overwhelming ma- 
jority of meaningful sentences lie, probabi- 
listically speaking, beyond the reach of ran- 
dom search. 

Denton (1986:301-324) and others have 
argued that similar constraints apply to 
genes and proteins. They have questioned 
whether an undirected search via mutation 
and selection would have a reasonable 
chance of locating new islands of func- 
tion — representing fundamentally new 
genes or proteins — within the time avail- 
able (Eden 1967, Shiitzenberger 1967, 
Lpvtrup 1979). Some have also argued that 
alterations in sequencing would likely result 
in loss of protein function before funda- 
mentally new function could arise (Eden 
1967, Denton 1986). Nevertheless, neither 
the extent to which genes and proteins are 
sensitive to functional loss as a result of 
sequence change, nor the extent to which 
functional proteins are isolated within se- 
quence space, has been fully known. 

Recently, experiments in molecular biol- 
ogy have shed light on these questions. A 
variety of mutagenesis techniques have 
shown that proteins (and thus the genes that 
produce them) are indeed highly specified 
relative to biological function (Bowie & 
Sauer 1989, Reidhaar-Olson & Sauer 1990, 
Taylor et al. 2001). Mutagenesis research 
tests the sensitivity of proteins (and, by im- 
plication, DNA) to functional loss as a result 
of alterations in sequencing. Studies of pro- 
teins have long shown that amino acid res- 



VOLUME 117, NUMBER 2 



219 



idues at many active positions cannot vary 
without functional loss (Perutz & Lehmann 
1968). More recent protein studies (often us- 
ing mutagenesis experiments) have shown 
that functional requirements place significant 
constraints on sequencing even at non-active 
site positions (Bowie & Sauer 1989, Reid- 
haar-Olson & Sauer 1990, Chothia et al. 
1998, Axe 2000, Taylor et al. 2001). In par- 
ticular, Axe (2000) has shown that multiple 
as opposed to single position amino acid 
substitutions inevitably result in loss of pro- 
tein function, even when these changes oc- 
cur at sites that allow variation when altered 
in isolation. Cumulatively, these constraints 
imply that proteins are highly sensitive to 
functional loss as a result of alterations in 
sequencing, and that functional proteins rep- 
resent highly isolated and improbable ar- 
rangements of amino acids — arrangements 
that are far more improbable, in fact, than 
would be likely to arise by chance alone in 
the time available (Reidhaar-Olson & Sauer 
1990; Behe 1992; Kauffman 1995:44; 
Dembski 1998:175-223; Axe 2000, 2004). 
(See below the discussion of the neutral the- 
ory of evolution for a precise quantitative 
assessment.) 

Of course, neo-Darwinists do not envi- 
sion a completely random search through 
the set of all possible nucleotide sequenc- 
es — so-called “sequence space.” They en- 
vision natural selection acting to preserve 
small advantageous variations in genetic se- 
quences and their corresponding protein 
products. Dawkins (1996), for example, lik- 
ens an organism to a high mountain peak. 
He compares climbing the sheer precipice 
up the front side of the mountain to build- 
ing a new organism by chance. He ac- 
knowledges that this approach up “Mount 
Improbable” will not succeed. Neverthe- 
less, he suggests that there is a gradual 
slope up the backside of the mountain that 
could be climbed in small incremental 
steps. In his analogy, the backside climb up 
“Mount Improbable” corresponds to the 
process of natural selection acting on ran- 
dom changes in the genetic text. What 



chance alone cannot accomplish blindly or 
in one leap, selection (acting on mutations) 
can accomplish through the cumulative ef- 
fect of many slight successive steps. 

Yet the extreme specificity and complex- 
ity of proteins presents a difficulty, not only 
for the chance origin of specified biological 
information (i.e., for random mutations act- 
ing alone), but also for selection and muta- 
tion acting in concert. Indeed, mutagenesis 
experiments cast doubt on each of the two 
scenarios by which neo-Darwinists envision 
new information arising from the mutation/ 
selection mechanism (for review, see Lonnig 
2001). For neo-Darwinism, new functional 
genes either arise from non-coding sections 
in the genome or from preexisting genes. 
Both scenarios are problematic. 

In the first scenario, neo-Darwinists en- 
vision new genetic information arising from 
those sections of the genetic text that can 
presumably vary freely without conse- 
quence to the organism. According to this 
scenario, non-coding sections of the ge- 
nome, or duplicated sections of coding re- 
gions, can experience a protracted period of 
“neutral evolution” (Kimura 1983) during 
which alterations in nucleotide sequences 
have no discernible effect on the function 
of the organism. Eventually, however, a 
new gene sequence will arise that can code 
for a novel protein. At that point, natural 
selection can favor the new gene and its 
functional protein product, thus securing 
the preservation and heritability of both. 

This scenario has the advantage of allow- 
ing the genome to vary through many gen- 
erations, as mutations “search” the space 
of possible base sequences. The scenario 
has an overriding problem, however: the 
size of the combinatorial space (i.e., the 
number of possible amino acid sequences) 
and the extreme rarity and isolation of the 
functional sequences within that space of 
possibilities. Since natural selection can do 
nothing to help generate new functional se- 
quences, but rather can only preserve such 
sequences once they have arisen, chance 
alone — random variation — must do the 



220 



PROCEEDINGS OF THE BIOLOGICAL SOCIETY OF WASHINGTON 



work of information generation — that is, of 
finding the exceedingly rare functional se- 
quences within the set of combinatorial 
possibilities. Yet the probability of random- 
ly assembling (or “finding,” in the previous 
sense) a functional sequence is extremely 
small. 

Cassette mutagenesis experiments per- 
formed during the early 1990s suggest that 
the probability of attaining (at random) the 
correct sequencing for a short protein 100 
amino acids long is about 1 in 10 65 (Reid- 
haar-Olson & Sauer 1990, Behe 1992:65- 
69). This result agreed closely with earlier 
calculations that Yockey (1978) had per- 
formed based upon the known sequence 
variability of cytochrome c in different spe- 
cies and other theoretical considerations. 
More recent mutagenesis research has pro- 
vided additional support for the conclusion 
that functional proteins are exceedingly rare 
among possible amino acid sequences (Axe 
2000, 2004). Axe (2004) has performed site 
directed mutagenesis experiments on a 150- 
residue protein-folding domain within a (3- 
lactamase enzyme. His experimental meth- 
od improves upon earlier mutagenesis tech- 
niques and corrects for several sources of 
possible estimation error inherent in them. 
On the basis of these experiments, Axe has 
estimated the ratio of (a) proteins of typical 
size (150 residues) that perform a specified 
function via any folded structure to (b) the 
whole set of possible amino acids sequenc- 
es of that size. Based on his experiments. 
Axe has estimated this ratio to be 1 to 10 77 . 
Thus, the probability of finding a functional 
protein among the possible amino acid se- 
quences corresponding to a 150-residue 
protein is similarly 1 in 10 77 . 

Other considerations imply additional 
improbabilities. First, new Cambrian ani- 
mals would require proteins much longer 
than 100 residues to perform many neces- 
sary specialized functions. Ohno (1996) has 
noted that Cambrian animals would have 
required complex proteins such as lysyl ox- 
idase in order to support their stout body 
structures. Lysyl oxidase molecules in ex- 



tant organisms comprise over 400 amino 
acids. These molecules are both highly 
complex (non-repetitive) and functionally 
specified. Reasonable extrapolation from 
mutagenesis experiments done on shorter 
protein molecules suggests that the proba- 
bility of producing functionally sequenced 
proteins of this length at random is so small 
as to make appeals to chance absurd, even 
granting the duration of the entire universe. 
(See Dembski 1998:175-223 for a rigorous 
calculation of this “Universal Probability 
Bound”; See also Axe 2004.) Yet, second, 
fossil data (Bowring et al. 1993, 1998a: 1, 
1998b:40; Kerr 1993; Monastersky 1993), 
and even molecular analyses supporting 
deep divergence (Wray et al. 1 996), suggest 
that the duration of the Cambrian explosion 
(between 5-10 X 10 6 and, at most, 7 X 10 7 
years) is far smaller than that of the entire 
universe (1.3—2 X 10 10 years). Third, DNA 
mutation rates are far too low to generate 
the novel genes and proteins necessary to 
building the Cambrian animals, given the 
most probable duration of the explosion as 
determined by fossil studies (Conway Mor- 
ris 1998b). As Ohno (1996:8475) notes, 
even a mutation rate of 10 -9 per base pair 
per year results in only a 1 % change in the 
sequence of a given section of DNA in 10 
million years. Thus, he argues that muta- 
tional divergence of pre-existing genes can- 
not explain the origin of the Cambrian 
forms in that time. 4 



4 To solve this problem Ohno himself proposes the 
existence of a hypothetical ancestral form that pos- 
sessed virtually all the genetic information necessary 
to produce the new body plans of the Cambrian ani- 
mals. He asserts that this ancestor and its “panani- 
malian genome” might have arisen several hundred 
million years before the Cambrian explosion. On this 
view, each of the different Cambrian animals would 
have possessed virtually identical genomes, albeit with 
considerable latent and unexpressed capacity in the 
case of each individual form (Ohno 1996:8475-8478). 
While this proposal might help explain the origin of 
the Cambrian animal forms by reference to pre-exist- 
ing genetic information, it does not solve, but instead 
merely displaces, the problem of the origin of the ge- 
netic information necessary to produce these new 
forms. 



VOLUME 117, NUMBER 2 



221 



The selection/mutation mechanism faces 
another probabilistic obstacle. The animals 
that arise in the Cambrian exhibit struc- 
tures that would have required many new 
types of cells, each of which would have 
required many novel proteins to perform 
their specialized functions. Further, new 
cell types require systems of proteins that 
must, as a condition of functioning, act in 
close coordination with one another. The 
unit of selection in such systems ascends 
to the system as a whole. Natural selection 
selects for functional advantage. But new 
cell types require whole systems of pro- 
teins to perform their distinctive functions. 
In such cases, natural selection cannot con- 
tribute to the process of information gen- 
eration until after the information neces- 
sary to build the requisite system of pro- 
teins has arisen. Thus random variations 
must, again, do the work of information 
generation — and now not simply for one 
protein, but for many proteins arising at 
nearly the same time. Yet the odds of this 
occurring by chance alone are, of course, 
far smaller than the odds of the chance or- 
igin of a single gene or protein — so small 
in fact as to render the chance origin of the 
genetic information necessary to build a 
new cell type (a necessary but not suffi- 
cient condition of building a new body 
plan) problematic given even the most op- 
timistic estimates for the duration of the 
Cambrian explosion. 

Dawkins (1986:139) has noted that sci- 
entific theories can rely on only so much 
“luck” before they cease to be credible. 
The neutral theory of evolution, which, by 
its own logic, prevents natural selection 
from playing a role in generating genetic 
information until after the fact, relies on 
entirely too much luck. The sensitivity of 
proteins to functional loss, the need for 
long proteins to build new cell types and 
animals, the need for whole new systems 
of proteins to service new cell types, the 
probable brevity of the Cambrian explo- 
sion relative to mutation rates — all suggest 
the immense improbability (and implausi- 



bility) of any scenario for the origination 
of Cambrian genetic information that relies 
upon random variation alone unassisted by 
natural selection. 

Yet the neutral theory requires novel 
genes and proteins to arise — essentially — 
by random mutation alone. Adaptive advan- 
tage accrues after the generation of new 
functional genes and proteins. Thus, natural 
selection cannot play a role until new in- 
formation-bearing molecules have indepen- 
dently arisen. Thus neutral theorists envi- 
sion the need to scale the steep face of a 
Dawkins-style precipice of which there is 
no gradually sloping backside — a situation 
that, by Dawkins’ own logic, is probabilis- 
tically untenable. 

In the second scenario, neo-Darwinists 
envision novel genes and proteins arising 
by numerous successive mutations in the 
preexisting genetic text that codes for pro- 
teins. To adapt Dawkins’s metaphor, this 
scenario envisions gradually climbing 
down one functional peak and then as- 
cending another. Yet mutagenesis experi- 
ments again suggest a difficulty. Recent 
experiments show that, even when explor- 
ing a region of sequence space populated 
by proteins of a single fold and function, 
most multiple-position changes quickly 
lead to loss of function (Axe 2000). Yet to 
turn one protein into another with a com- 
pletely novel structure and function re- 
quires specified changes at many sites. In- 
deed, the number of changes necessary to 
produce a new protein greatly exceeds the 
number of changes that will typically pro- 
duce functional losses. Given this, the 
probability of escaping total functional 
loss during a random search for the chang- 
es needed to produce a new function is ex- 
tremely small — and this probability dimin- 
ishes exponentially with each additional 
requisite change (Axe 2000). Thus, Axe’s 
results imply that, in all probability, ran- 
dom searches for novel proteins (through 
sequence space) will result in functional 
loss long before any novel functional pro- 
tein will emerge. 



222 



PROCEEDINGS OF THE BIOLOGICAL SOCIETY OF WASHINGTON 



Blanco et al. have come to a similar con- 
clusion. Using directed mutagenesis, they 
have determined that residues in both the 
hydrophobic core and on the surface of the 
protein play essential roles in determining 
protein structure. By sampling intermediate 
sequences between two naturally occurring 
sequences that adopt different folds, they 
found that the intermediate sequences “lack 
a well defined three-dimensional structure.” 
Thus, they conclude that it is unlikely that 
a new protein fold would evolve from a 
pre-existing fold via a series of folded in- 
termediates sequences (Blanco et al. 1999: 
741). 

Thus, although this second neo-Darwin- 
ian scenario has the advantage of starting 
with functional genes and proteins, it also 
has a lethal disadvantage: any process of 
random mutation or rearrangement in the 
genome would in all probability generate 
nonfunctional intermediate sequences be- 
fore fundamentally new functional genes or 
proteins would arise. Clearly, nonfunctional 
intermediate sequences confer no survival 
advantage on their host organisms. Natural 
selection favors only functional advantage. 
It cannot select or favor nucleotide se- 
quences or polypeptide chains that do not 
yet perform biological functions, and still 
less will it favor sequences that efface or 
destroy preexisting function. 

Evolving genes and proteins will range 
through a series of nonfunctional interme- 
diate sequences that natural selection will 
not favor or preserve but will, in all prob- 
ability, eliminate (Blanco et al. 1999, Axe 
2000). When this happens, selection-driven 
evolution will cease. At this point, neutral 
evolution of the genome (unhinged from se- 
lective pressure) may ensue, but, as we 
have seen, such a process must overcome 
immense probabilistic hurdles, even grant- 
ing cosmic time. 

Thus, whether one envisions the evolu- 
tionary process beginning with a noncoding 
region of the genome or a preexisting func- 
tional gene, the functional specificity and 
complexity of proteins impose very strin- 



gent limitations on the efficacy of mutation 
and selection. In the first case, function 
must arise first, before natural selection can 
act to favor a novel variation. In the second 
case, function must be continuously main- 
tained in order to prevent deleterious (or le- 
thal) consequences to the organism and to 
allow further evolution. Yet the complexity 
and functional specificity of proteins im- 
plies that both these conditions will be ex- 
tremely difficult to meet. Therefore, the 
neo-Darwinian mechanism appears to be 
inadequate to generate the new information 
present in the novel genes and proteins that 
arise with the Cambrian animals. 

Novel Body Plans 

The problems with the neo-Darwinian 
mechanism run deeper still. In order to ex- 
plain the origin of the Cambrian animals, 
one must account not only for new proteins 
and cell types, but also for the origin of new 
body plans. Within the past decade, devel- 
opmental biology has dramatically ad- 
vanced our understanding of how body 
plans are built during ontogeny. In the pro- 
cess, it has also uncovered a profound dif- 
ficulty for neo-Darwinism. 

Significant morphological change in or- 
ganisms requires attention to timing. Mu- 
tations in genes that are expressed late in 
the development of an organism will not 
affect the body plan. Mutations expressed 
early in development, however, could con- 
ceivably produce significant morphological 
change (Arthur 1997:21). Thus, events ex- 
pressed early in the development of organ- 
isms have the only realistic chance of pro- 
ducing large-scale macroevolutionary 
change (Thomson 1992). As John and Mik- 
los (1988:309) explain, macroevolutionary 
change requires alterations in the very early 
stages of ontogenesis. 

Yet recent studies in developmental bi- 
ology make clear that mutations expressed 
early in development typically have dele- 
terious effects (Arthur 1997:21). For ex- 
ample, when early-acting body plan mol- 



VOLUME 1 17, NUMBER 2 



223 



ecules, or morphogens such as bicoid 
(which helps to set up the anterior-poste- 
rior head-to-tail axis in Drosophila), are 
perturbed, development shuts down (Niis- 
slein-Volhard & Wieschaus 1980, Lawr- 
ence & Struhl 1996, Muller & Newman 
2003). 5 The resulting embryos die. More- 
over, there is a good reason for this. If an 
engineer modifies the length of the piston 
rods in an internal combustion engine 
without modifying the crankshaft accord- 
ingly, the engine won’t start. Similarly, 
processes of development are tightly inte- 
grated spatially and temporally such that 
changes early in development will require 
a host of other coordinated changes in sep- 
arate but functionally interrelated devel- 
opmental processes downstream. For this 
reason, mutations will be much more likely 
to be deadly if they disrupt a functionally 
deeply-embedded structure such as a spinal 
column than if they affect more isolated 
anatomical features such as fingers (Kauff- 
man 1995:200). 

This problem has led to what McDonald 
(1983) has called “a great Darwinian par- 
adox” (p. 93). McDonald notes that genes 
that are observed to vary within natural 
populations do not lead to major adaptive 
changes, while genes that could cause ma- 
jor changes — the very stuff of macroevo- 
lution — apparently do not vary. In other 
words, mutations of the kind that macro- 
evolution doesn’t need (namely, viable ge- 
netic mutations in DNA expressed late in 
development) do occur, but those that it 
does need (namely, beneficial body plan 
mutations expressed early in development) 



5 Some have suggested that mutations in “master 
regulator” Hox genes might provide the raw material 
for body plan morphogenesis. Yet there are two prob- 
lems with this proposal. First, Hox gene expression 
begins only after the foundation of the body plan has 
been established in early embryogenesis (Davidson 
2001:66). Second, Hox genes are highly conserved 
across many disparate phyla and so cannot account for 
the morphological differences that exist between the 
phyla (Valentine 2004:88). 



apparently don’t occur. 6 According to Dar- 
win (1859:108) natural selection cannot act 
until favorable variations arise in a popu- 
lation. Yet there is no evidence from de- 
velopmental genetics that the kind of vari- 
ations required by neo-Darwinism — name- 
ly, favorable body plan mutations — ever 
occur. 

Developmental biology has raised anoth- 
er formidable problem for the mutation/se- 
lection mechanism. Embryological evi- 
dence has long shown that DNA does not 
wholly determine morphological form 
(Goodwin 1985, Nijhout 1990, Sapp 1987, 
Muller & Newman 2003), suggesting that 
mutations in DNA alone cannot account for 
the morphological changes required to build 
a new body plan. 

DNA helps directs protein synthesis. 7 It 
also helps to regulate the timing and ex- 
pression of the synthesis of various proteins 
within cells. Yet, DNA alone does not de- 
termine how individual proteins assemble 
themselves into larger systems of proteins; 
still less does it solely determine how cell 
types, tissue types, and organs arrange 
themselves into body plans (Harold 1995: 



6 Notable differences in the developmental pathways 
of similar organisms have been observed. For exam- 
ple, congeneric species of sea urchins (from genus He- 
liocidaris ) exhibit striking differences in their devel- 
opmental pathways (Raff 1999:110-121). Thus, it 
might be argued that such differences show that early 
developmental programs can in fact be mutated to pro- 
duce new forms. Nevertheless, there are two problems 
with this claim. First, there is no direct evidence that 
existing differences in sea urchin development arose 
by mutation. Second, the observed differences in the 
developmental programs of different species of sea ur- 
chins do not result in new body plans, but instead in 
highly conserved structures. Despite differences in de- 
velopmental patterns, the endpoints are the same. 
Thus, even if it can be assumed that mutations pro- 
duced the differences in developmental pathways, it 
must be acknowledged that such changes did not result 
in novel form. 

7 Of course, many post-translation processes of 
modification also play a role in producing a functional 
protein. Such processes make it impossible to predict 
a protein’s final sequencing from its corresponding 
gene sequence alone (Sarkar 1996:199-202). 



224 



PROCEEDINGS OF THE BIOLOGICAL SOCIETY OF WASHINGTON 



2774, Moss 2004). Instead, other factors — 
such as the three-dimensional structure and 
organization of the cell membrane and cy- 
toskeleton and the spatial architecture of the 
fertilized egg — play important roles in de- 
termining body plan formation during em- 
bryogenesis. 

For example, the structure and location 
of the cytoskeleton influence the patterning 
of embryos. Arrays of microtubules help to 
distribute the essential proteins used during 
development to their correct locations in the 
cell. Of course, microtubules themselves 
are made of many protein subunits. Nev- 
ertheless, like bricks that can be used to as- 
semble many different structures, the tu- 
bulin subunits in the cell’s microtubules are 
identical to one another. Thus, neither the 
tubulin subunits nor the genes that produce 
them account for the different shape of mi- 
crotubule arrays that distinguish different 
kinds of embryos and developmental path- 
ways. Instead, the structure of the micro- 
tubule array itself is determined by the lo- 
cation and arrangement of its subunits, not 
the properties of the subunits themselves. 
For this reason, it is not possible to predict 
the structure of the cytoskeleton of the cell 
from the characteristics of the protein con- 
stituents that form that structure (Harold 
2001:125). 

Two analogies may help further clarify 
the point. At a building site, builders will 
make use of many materials: lumber, wires, 
nails, drywall, piping, and windows. Yet 
building materials do not determine the 
floor plan of the house, or the arrangement 
of houses in a neighborhood. Similarly, 
electronic circuits are composed of many 
components, such as resistors, capacitors, 
and transistors. But such lower-level com- 
ponents do not determine their own ar- 
rangement in an integrated circuit. Biolog- 
ical systems also depend on hierarchical ar- 
rangements of parts. Genes and proteins are 
made from simple building blocks — nucle- 
otide bases and amino acids — arranged in 
specific ways. Cell types are made of, 
among other things, systems of specialized 



proteins. Organs are made of specialized ar- 
rangements of cell types and tissues. And 
body plans comprise specific arrangements 
of specialized organs. Yet, clearly, the prop- 
erties of individual proteins (or, indeed, the 
lower-level parts in the hierarchy generally) 
do not fully determine the organization of 
the higher-level structures and organization- 
al patterns (Harold 2001:125). It follows 
that the genetic information that codes for 
proteins does not determine these higher- 
level structures either. 

These considerations pose another chal- 
lenge to the sufficiency of the neo-Darwin- 
ian mechanism. Neo-Darwinism seeks to 
explain the origin of new information, 
form, and structure as a result of selection 
acting on randomly arising variation at a 
very low level within the biological hier- 
archy, namely, within the genetic text. Yet 
major morphological innovations depend 
on a specificity of arrangement at a much 
higher level of the organizational hierarchy, 
a level that DNA alone does not determine. 
Yet if DNA is not wholly responsible for 
body plan morphogenesis, then DNA se- 
quences can mutate indefinitely, without re- 
gard to realistic probabilistic limits, and still 
not produce a new body plan. Thus, the 
mechanism of natural selection acting on 
random mutations in DNA cannot in prin- 
ciple generate novel body plans, including 
those that first arose in the Cambrian ex- 
plosion. 

Of course, it could be argued that, while 
many single proteins do not by themselves 
determine cellular structures and/or body 
plans, proteins acting in concert with other 
proteins or suites of proteins could deter- 
mine such higher-level form. For example, 
it might be pointed out that the tubulin sub- 
units (cited above) are assembled by other 
helper proteins — gene products — called Mi- 
crotubule Associated Proteins (MAPS). 
This might seem to suggest that genes and 
gene products alone do suffice to determine 
the development of the three-dimensional 
structure of the cytoskeleton. 

Yet, MAPS, and indeed many other nec- 



VOLUME 117, NUMBER 2 



225 



essary proteins, are only part of the story. 
The location of specified target sites on the 
interior of the cell membrane also helps to 
determine the shape of the cytoskeleton. 
Similarly, so does the position and structure 
of the centrosome which nucleates the mi- 
crotubules that form the cytoskeleton. 
While both the membrane targets and the 
centrosomes are made of proteins, the lo- 
cation and form of these structures is not 
wholly determined by the proteins that form 
them. Indeed, centrosome structure and 
membrane patterns as a whole convey 
three-dimensional structural information 
that helps determine the structure of the cy- 
toskeleton and the location of its subunits 
(McNiven & Porter 1992:313-329). More- 
over, the centrioles that compose the cen- 
trosomes replicate independently of DNA 
replication (Lange et al. 2000:235-249, 
Marshall & Rosenbaum 2000:187-205). 
The daughter centriole receives its form 
from the overall structure of the mother 
centriole, not from the individual gene 
products that constitute it (Lange et al. 
2000). In ciliates, microsurgery on cell 
membranes can produce heritable changes 
in membrane patterns, even though the 
DNA of the ciliates has not been altered 
(Sonneborn 1970:1-13, Frankel 1980:607- 
623; Nanney 1983:163-170). This suggests 
that membrane patterns (as opposed to 
membrane constituents) are impressed di- 
rectly on daughter cells. In both cases, form 
is transmitted from parent three-dimension- 
al structures to daughter three-dimensional 
structures directly and is not wholly con- 
tained in constituent proteins or genetic in- 
formation (Moss 2004). 

Thus, in each new generation, the form 
and structure of the cell arises as the result 
of both gene products and pre-existing 
three-dimensional structure and organiza- 
tion. Cellular structures are built from pro- 
teins, but proteins find their way to correct 
locations in part because of pre-existing 
three-dimensional patterns and organization 
inherent in cellular structures. Pre-existing 
three-dimensional form present in the pre- 



ceding generation (whether inherent in the 
cell membrane, the centrosomes, the cyto- 
skeleton or other features of the fertilized 
egg) contributes to the production of form 
in the next generation. Neither structural 
proteins alone, nor the genes that code for 
them, are sufficient to determine the three- 
dimensional shape and structure of the en- 
tities they form. Gene products provide nec- 
essary, but not sufficient conditions, for the 
development of three-dimensional structure 
within cells, organs and body plans (Harold 
1995:2767). But if this is so, then natural 
selection acting on genetic variation alone 
cannot produce the new forms that arise in 
history of life. 

Self-Organizational Models 

Of course, neo-Darwinism is not the only 
evolutionary theory for explaining the ori- 
gin of novel biological form. Kauffman 
(1995) doubts the efficacy of the mutation/ 
selection mechanism. Nevertheless, he has 
advanced a self-organizational theory to ac- 
count for the emergence of new form, and 
presumably the information necessary to 
generate it. Whereas neo-Darwinism at- 
tempts to explain new form as the conse- 
quence of selection acting on random mu- 
tation, Kauffman suggests that selection 
acts, not mainly on random variations, but 
on emergent patterns of order that self- 
organize via the laws of nature. 

Kauffman (1995:47-92) illustrates how 
this might work with various model sys- 
tems in a computer environment. In one, he 
conceives a system of buttons connected by 
strings. Buttons represent novel genes or 
gene products; strings represent the law-like 
forces of interaction that obtain between 
gene products — i.e., proteins. Kauffman 
suggests that when the complexity of the 
system (as represented by the number of 
buttons and strings) reaches a critical 
threshold, new modes of organization can 
arise in the system “for free” — that is, nat- 
urally and spontaneously — after the manner 
of a phase transition in chemistry. 



226 



PROCEEDINGS OF THE BIOLOGICAL SOCIETY OF WASHINGTON 



Another model that Kauffman develops 
is a system of interconnected lights. Each 
light can flash in a variety of states— on, 
off, twinkling, etc. Since there is more than 
one possible state for each light, and many 
lights, there are a vast number of possible 
states that the system can adopt. Further, in 
his system, rules determine how past states 
will influence future states. Kauffman as- 
serts that, as a result of these rules, the sys- 
tem will, if properly tuned, eventually pro- 
duce a kind of order in which a few basic 
patterns of light activity recur with greater- 
than-random frequency. Since these actual 
patterns of light activity represent a small 
portion of the total number of possible 
states in which the system can reside, Kauf- 
man seems to imply that self-organizational 
laws might similarly result in highly im- 
probable biological outcomes— perhaps 
even sequences (of bases or amino acids) 
within a much larger sequence space of 
possibilities. 

Do these simulations of self-organiza- 
tional processes accurately model the origin 
of novel genetic information? It is hard to 
think so. 

First, in both examples, Kaufmann pre- 
supposes but does not explain significant 
sources of preexisting information. In his 
buttons-and-strings system, the buttons rep- 
resent proteins, themselves packets of CSI, 
and the result of pre-existing genetic infor- 
mation. Where does this information come 
from? Kauffman (1995) doesn’t say, but the 
origin of such information is an essential 
part of what needs to be explained in the 
history of life. Similarly, in his light sys- 
tem, the order that allegedly arises for “for 
free” actually arises only if the programmer 
of the model system “tunes” it in such a 
way as to keep it from either (a) generating 
an excessively rigid order or (b) devolving 
into chaos (pp. 86-88). Yet this necessary 
tuning involves an intelligent programmer 
selecting certain parameters and excluding 
others — that is, inputting information. 

Second, Kauffman’s model systems are 
not constrained by functional consider- 



ations and thus are not analogous to biolog- 
ical systems. A system of interconnected 
lights governed by pre-programmed rules 
may well settle into a small number of pat- 
terns within a much larger space of possi- 
bilities. But because these patterns have no 
function, and need not meet any functional 
requirements, they have no specificity anal- 
ogous to that present in actual organisms. 
Instead, examination of Kauffman’s (1995) 
model systems shows that they do not pro- 
duce sequences or systems characterized by 
specified complexity, but instead by large 
amounts of symmetrical order or internal 
redundancy interspersed with aperiodicity 
or (mere) complexity (pp. 53, 89, 102). Get- 
ting a law-governed system to generate re- 
petitive patterns of flashing lights, even 
with a certain amount of variation, is clearly 
interesting, but not biologically relevant. 
On the other hand, a system of lights flash- 
ing the title of a Broadway play would 
model a biologically relevant self-organi- 
zational process, at least if such a meaning- 
ful or functionally specified sequence arose 
without intelligent agents previously pro- 
gramming the system with equivalent 
amounts of CSI. In any case, Kauffman’s 
systems do not produce specified complex- 
ity, and thus do not offer promising models 
for explaining the new genes and proteins 
that arose in the Cambrian. 

Even so, Kauffman suggests that his self- 
organizational models can specifically elu- 
cidate aspects of the Cambrian explosion. 
According to Kauffman (1995:199-201), 
new Cambrian animals emerged as the re- 
sult of “long jump” mutations that estab- 
lished new body plans in a discrete rather 
than gradual fashion. He also recognizes 
that mutations affecting early development 
are almost inevitably harmful. Thus, he 
concludes that body plans, once established, 
will not change, and that any subsequent 
evolution must occur within an established 
body plan (Kauffman 1995:201). And in- 
deed, the fossil record does show a curious 
(from a neo-Darwinian point of view) top- 
down pattern of appearance, in which high- 



VOLUME 1 17, NUMBER 2 



227 



er taxa (and the body plans they represent) 
appear first, only later to be followed by the 
multiplication of lower taxa representing 
variations within those original body de- 
signs (Erwin et al. 1987, Lewin 1988, Val- 
entine & Jablonski 2003:518). Further, as 
Kauffman expects, body plans appear sud- 
denly and persist without significant modi- 
fication over time. 

But here, again, Kauffman begs the most 
important question, which is: what produc- 
es the new Cambrian body plans in the first 
place? Granted, he invokes “long jump mu- 
tations” to explain this, but he identifies no 
specific self-organizational process that can 
produce such mutations. Moreover, he con- 
cedes a principle that undermines the plau- 
sibility of his own proposal. Kauffman ac- 
knowledges that mutations that occur early 
in development are almost inevitably dele- 
terious. Yet developmental biologists know 
that these are the only kind of mutations 
that have a realistic chance of producing 
large-scale evolutionary change — i.e., the 
big jumps that Kauffman invokes. Though 
Kauffman repudiates the neo-Darwinian re- 
liance upon random mutations in favor of 
self-organizing order, in the end, he must 
invoke the most implausible kind of ran- 
dom mutation in order to provide a self- 
organizational account of the new Cambri- 
an body plans. Clearly, his model is not suf- 
ficient. 

Punctuated Equilibrium 

Of course, still other causal explanations 
have been proposed. During the 1970s, the 
paleontologists Eldredge and Gould (1972) 
proposed the theory of evolution by punc- 
tuated equilibrium in order to account for a 
pervasive pattern of “sudden appearance” 
and “stasis” in the fossil record. Though 
advocates of punctuated equilibrium were 
mainly seeking to describe the fossil record 
more accurately than earlier gradualist neo- 
Darwinian models had done, they did also 
propose a mechanism — known as species 
selection — by which the large morphologi- 



cal jumps evident in fossil record might 
have been produced. According to punctua- 
tionalists, natural selection functions more 
as a mechanism for selecting the fittest spe- 
cies rather than the most-fit individual 
among a species. Accordingly, on this mod- 
el, morphological change should occur in 
larger, more discrete intervals than it would 
given a traditional neo-Darwinian under- 
standing. 

Despite its virtues as a descriptive model 
of the history of life, punctuated equilibri- 
um has been widely criticized for failing to 
provide a mechanism sufficient to produce 
the novel form characteristic of higher tax- 
onomic groups. For one thing, critics have 
noted that the proposed mechanism of 
punctuated evolutionary change simply 
lacked the raw material upon which to 
work. As Valentine and Erwin (1987) note, 
the fossil record fails to document a large 
pool of species prior to the Cambrian. Yet 
the proposed mechanism of species selec- 
tion requires just such a pool of species 
upon which to act. Thus, they conclude that 
the mechanism of species selection proba- 
bly does not resolve the problem of the or- 
igin of the higher taxonomic groups (p. 
96). 8 Further, punctuated equilibrium has 
not addressed the more specific and fun- 
damental problem of explaining the origin 
of the new biological information (whether 
genetic or epigenetic) necessary to produce 
novel biological form. Advocates of punc- 
tuated equilibrium might assume that the 
new species (upon which natural selection 
acts) arise by known micro-evolutionary 
processes of speciation (such as founder ef- 



8 Erwin (2004:21), although friendly to the possibil- 
ity of species selection, argues that Gould provides lit- 
tle evidence for its existence. “The difficulty” writes 
Erwin of species selection, “. . . is that we must rely 
on Gould’s arguments for theoretical plausibility and 
sufficient relative frequency. Rarely is a mass of data 
presented to justify and support Gould’s conclusion.” 
Indeed, Gould (2002) himself admitted that species se- 
lection remains largely a hypothetical construct: “I 
freely admit that well-documented cases of species se- 
lection do not permeate the literature” (p. 710). 



228 



PROCEEDINGS OF THE BIOLOGICAL SOCIETY OF WASHINGTON 



feet, genetic drift or bottleneck effect) that 
do not necessarily depend upon mutations 
to produce adaptive changes. But, in that 
case, the theory lacks an account of how 
the specifically higher taxa arise. Species 
selection will only produce more fit species. 
On the other hand, if punctuationalists as- 
sume that processes of genetic mutation can 
produce more fundamental morphological 
changes and variations, then their model be- 
comes subject to the same problems as neo- 
Darwinism (see above). This dilemma is 
evident in Gould (2002:710) insofar as his 
attempts to explain adaptive complexity in- 
evitably employ classical neo-Darwinian 
modes of explanation. 9 

Structuralism 

Another attempt to explain the origin of 
form has been proposed by the structuralists 
such as Gerry Webster and Brian Goodwin 
(1984, 1996). These biologists, drawing on 
the earlier work of D’Arcy Thompson 
(1942), view biological form as the result 
of structural constraints imposed upon mat- 
ter by morphogenetic rules or laws. For rea- 
sons similar to those discussed above, the 
structuralists have insisted that these gen- 
erative or morphogenetic rules do not reside 
in the lower level building materials of or- 



9 “I do not deny either the wonder, or the powerful 
importance, of organized adaptive complexity. I rec- 
ognize that we know no mechanism for the origin of 
such organismal features other than conventional nat- 
ural selection at the organismic level — for the sheer 
intricacy and elaboration of good biomechanical de- 
sign surely precludes either random production, or in- 
cidental origin as a side consequence of active pro- 
cesses at other levels” (Gould 2002:710). “Thus, we 
do not challenge the efficacy or the cardinal impor- 
tance of organismal selection. As previously discussed, 
I fully agree with Dawkins (1986) and others that one 
cannot invoke a higher-level force like species selec- 
tion to explain ‘things that organisms do’ — in partic- 
ular, the stunning panoply of organismic adaptations 
that has always motivated our sense of wonder about 
the natural world, and that Darwin (1859) described, 
in one of his most famous lines (3), as ‘that perfection 
of structure and coadaptation which most justly excites 
our admiration’ ” (Gould 2002:886). 



ganisms, whether in genes or proteins. 
Webster and Goodwin (1984:510-511) fur- 
ther envision morphogenetic rules or laws 
operating ahistorically, similar to the way 
in which gravitational or electro-magnetic 
laws operate. For this reason, structuralists 
see phylogeny as of secondary importance 
in understanding the origin of the higher 
taxa, though they think that transformations 
of form can occur. For structuralists, con- 
straints on the arrangement of matter arise 
not mainly as the result of historical contin- 
gencies — such as environmental changes or 
genetic mutations — but instead because of 
the continuous ahistorical operation of fun- 
damental laws of form — laws that organize 
or inform matter. 

While this approach avoids many of the 
difficulties currently afflicting neo-Darwin- 
ism (in particular those associated with its 
“genocentricity”), critics (such as Maynard 
Smith 1986) of structuralism have argued 
that the structuralist explanation of form 
lacks specificity. They note that structural- 
ists have been unable to say just where laws 
of form reside — whether in the universe, or 
in every possible world, or in organisms as 
a whole, or in just some part of organisms. 
Further, according to structuralists, morpho- 
genetic laws are mathematical in character. 
Yet, structuralists have yet to specify the 
mathematical formulae that determine bio- 
logical forms. 

Others (Yockey 1992; Polanyi 1967, 
1968; Meyer 2003) have questioned wheth- 
er physical laws could in principle generate 
the kind of complexity that characterizes bi- 
ological systems. Structuralists envision the 
existence of biological laws that produce 
form in much the same way that physical 
laws produce form. Yet the forms that phys- 
icists regard as manifestations of underlying 
laws are characterized by large amounts of 
symmetric or redundant order, by relatively 
simple patterns such as vortices or gravi- 
tational fields or magnetic lines of force. In- 
deed, physical laws are typically expressed 
as differential equations (or algorithms) that 
almost by definition describe recurring phe- 



VOLUME 117, NUMBER 2 



229 



nomena — patterns of compressible “order” 
not “complexity” as defined by algorithmic 
information theory (Yockey 1992:77-83). 
Biological forms, by contrast, manifest 
greater complexity and derive in ontogeny 
from highly complex initial conditions — 
i.e., non-redundant sequences of nucleotide 
bases in the genome and other forms of in- 
formation expressed in the complex and ir- 
regular three-dimensional topography of the 
organism or the fertilized egg. Thus, the 
kind of form that physical laws produce is 
not analogous to biological form — at least 
not when compared from the standpoint of 
(algorithmic) complexity. Further, physical 
laws lack the information content to specify 
biology systems. As Polanyi (1967, 1968) 
and Yockey (1992:290) have shown, the 
laws of physics and chemistry allow, but do 
not determine, distinctively biological 
modes of organization. In other words, liv- 
ing systems are consistent with, but not de- 
ducible, from physical-chemical laws 
(1992:290). 

Of course, biological systems do manifest 
some reoccurring patterns, processes and be- 
haviors. The same type of organism devel- 
ops repeatedly from similar ontogenetic pro- 
cesses in the same species. Similar processes 
of cell division re-occur in many organisms. 
Thus, one might describe certain biological 
processes as law-governed. Even so, the ex- 
istence of such biological regularities does 
not solve the problem of the origin of form 
and information, since the recurring process- 
es described by such biological laws (if there 
be such laws) only occur as the result of pre- 
existing stores of (genetic and/or epigenetic) 
information and these information-rich ini- 
tial conditions impose the constraints that 
produce the recurring behavior in biological 
systems. (For example, processes of cell di- 
vision recur with great frequency in organ- 
isms, but depend upon information-rich 
DNA and proteins molecules.) In other 
words, distinctively biological regularities 
depend upon pre-existing biological infor- 
mation. Thus, appeals to higher-level biolog- 
ical laws presuppose, but do not explain, the 



origination of the information necessary to 
morphogenesis. 

Thus, structuralism faces a difficult in 
principle dilemma. On the one hand, phys- 
ical laws produce very simple redundant 
patterns that lack the complexity character- 
istic of biological systems. On the other 
hand, distinctively biological laws — if there 
are such laws — depend upon pre-existing 
information-rich structures. In either case, 
laws are not good candidates for explaining 
the origination of biological form or the in- 
formation necessary to produce it. 

Cladism: An Artifact of Classification? 

Some cladists have advanced another ap- 
proach to the problem of the origin of form, 
specifically as it arises in the Cambrian. 
They have argued that the problem of the 
origin of the phyla is an artifact of the clas- 
sification system, and therefore, does not 
require explanation. Budd and Jensen 
(2000), for example, argue that the problem 
of the Cambrian explosion resolves itself if 
one keeps in mind the cladistic distinction 
between “stem” and “crown” groups. 
Since crown groups arise whenever new 
characters are added to simpler more an- 
cestral stem groups during the evolutionary 
process, new phyla will inevitably arise 
once a new stem group has arisen. Thus, 
for Budd and Jensen what requires expla- 
nation is not the crown groups correspond- 
ing to the new Cambrian phyla, but the ear- 
lier more primitive stem groups that pre- 
sumably arose deep in the Proterozoic. Yet 
since these earlier stem groups are by def- 
inition less derived, explaining them will be 
considerably easier than explaining the or- 
igin of the Cambrian animals de novo. In 
any case, for Budd and Jensen the explo- 
sion of new phyla in the Cambrian does not 
require explanation. As they put it, “given 
that the early branching points of major 
clades is an inevitable result of clade di- 
versification, the alleged phenomenon of 
the phyla appearing early and remaining 
morphologically static is not seen to require 



230 



PROCEEDINGS OF THE BIOLOGICAL SOCIETY OF WASHINGTON 



particular explanation” (Budd & Jensen 
2000:253). 

While superficially plausible, perhaps, 
Budd and Jensen’s attempt to explain away 
the Cambrian explosion begs crucial ques- 
tions. Granted, as new characters are added 
to existing forms, novel morphology and 
greater morphological disparity will likely 
result. But what causes new characters to 
arise? And how does the information nec- 
essary to produce new characters originate? 
Budd and Jensen do not specify. Nor can 
they say how derived the ancestral forms 
are likely to have been, and what processes, 
might have been sufficient to produce them. 
Instead, they simply assume the sufficiency 
of known neo-Darwinian mechanisms 
(Budd & Jensen 2000:288). Yet, as shown 
above, this assumption is now problematic. 
In any case, Budd and Jensen do not ex- 
plain what causes the origination of biolog- 
ical form and information. 

Convergence and Teleological Evolution 

More recently, Conway Morris (2000, 
2003c) has suggested another possible ex- 
planation based on the tendency for evolu- 
tion to converge on the same structural 
forms during the history of life. Conway 
Morris cites numerous examples of organ- 
isms that possess very similar forms and 
structures, even though such structures are 
often built from different material sub- 
strates and arise (in ontogeny) by the ex- 
pression of very different genes. Given the 
extreme improbability of the same struc- 
tures arising by random mutation and se- 
lection in disparate phytogenies, Conway 
Morris argues that the pervasiveness of 
convergent structures suggests that evolu- 
tion may be in some way “channeled” to- 
ward similar functional and/or structural 
endpoints. Such an end-directed under- 
standing of evolution, he admits, raises the 
controversial prospect of a teleological or 
purposive element in the history of life. For 
this reason, he argues that the phenomenon 
of convergence has received less attention 



than it might have otherwise. Nevertheless, 
he argues that just as physicists have re- 
opened the question of design in their dis- 
cussions of anthropic fine-tuning, the ubiq- 
uity of convergent structures in the history 
of life has led some biologists (Denton 
1998) to consider extending teleological 
thinking to biology. And, indeed, Conway 
Morris himself intimates that the evolution- 
ary process might be “underpinned by a 
purpose” (2000:8, 2003b:511). 

Conway Morris, of course, considers this 
possibility in relation to a very specific as- 
pect of the problem of organismal form, 
namely, the problem of explaining why the 
same forms arise repeatedly in so many dis- 
parate lines of decent. But this raises a 
question. Could a similar approach shed ex- 
planatory light on the more general causal 
question that has been addressed in this re- 
view? Could the notion of purposive design 
help provide a more adequate explanation 
for the origin of organismal form generally? 
Are there reasons to consider design as an 
explanation for the origin of the biological 
information necessary to produce the higher 
taxa and their corresponding morphological 
novelty? 

The remainder of this review will suggest 
that there are such reasons. In so doing, it 
may also help explain why the issue of tel- 
eology or design has re-emerged within the 
scientific discussion of biological origins 
(Denton 1986, 1998; Thaxton et al. 1992; 
Kenyon & Mills 1996; Behe 1996, 2004; 
Dembski 1998, 2002, 2004; Conway Mor- 
ris 2000, 2003a, 2003b; Lonnig 2001; Lon- 
nig & Saedler 2002; Nelson & Wells 2003; 
Meyer 2003, 2004; Bradley 2004) and why 
some scientists and philosophers of science 
have considered teleological explanations 
for the origin of form and information de- 
spite strong methodological prohibitions 
against design as a scientific hypothesis 
(Gillespie 1979, Lenior 1982:4). 

First, the possibility of design as an ex- 
planation follows logically from a consid- 
eration of the deficiencies of neo-Darwin- 
ism and other current theories as explana- 



VOLUME 117, NUMBER 2 



231 



tions for some of the more striking “ap- 
pearances of design” in biological systems. 
Neo-Darwinists such as Ayala (1994:5), 
Dawkins (1986:1), Mayr (1982:xi-xii) and 
Lewontin (1978) have long acknowledged 
that organisms appear to have been de- 
signed. Of course, neo-Darwinists assert 
that what Ayala (1994:5) calls the “obvious 
design” of living things is only apparent 
since the selection/mutation mechanism can 
explain the origin of complex form and or- 
ganization in living systems without an ap- 
peal to a designing agent. Indeed, neo-Dar- 
winists affirm that mutation and selection — 
and perhaps other similarly undirected 
mechanisms — are fully sufficient to explain 
the appearance of design in biology. Self- 
organizational theorists and punctuational- 
ists modify this claim, but affirm its essen- 
tial tenet. Self-organization theorists argue 
that natural selection acting on self-organiz- 
ing order can explain the complexity of liv- 
ing things — again, without any appeal to 
design. Punctuationalists similarly envision 
natural selection acting on newly arising 
species with no actual design involved. 

And clearly, the neo-Darwinian mecha- 
nism does explain many appearances of de- 
sign, such as the adaptation of organisms to 
specialized environments that attracted the 
interest of 19th century biologists. More 
specifically, known micro-evolutionary pro- 
cesses appear quite sufficient to account for 
changes in the size of Galapagos finch 
beaks that have occurred in response to var- 
iations in annual rainfall and available food 
supplies (Weiner 1994, Grant 1999). 

But does neo-Darwinism, or any other 
fully materialistic model, explain all ap- 
pearances of design in biology, including 
the body plans and information that char- 
acterize living systems? Arguably, biologi- 
cal forms — such as the structure of a cham- 
bered nautilus, the organization of a trilo- 
bite, the functional integration of parts in 
an eye or molecular machine — attract our 
attention in part because the organized 
complexity of such systems seems reminis- 
cent of our own designs. Yet, this review 



has argued that neo-Darwinism does not 
adequately account for the origin of all ap- 
pearances of design, especially if one con- 
siders animal body plans, and the informa- 
tion necessary to construct them, as espe- 
cially striking examples of the appearance 
of design in living systems. Indeed, Dawk- 
ins (1995:11) and Gates (1996:228) have 
noted that genetic information bears an un- 
canny resemblance to computer software or 
machine code. For this reason, the presence 
of CSI in living organisms, and the discon- 
tinuous increases of CSI that occurred dur- 
ing events such as the Cambrian explosion, 
appears at least suggestive of design. 

Does neo-Darwinism or any other purely 
materialistic model of morphogenesis ac- 
count for the origin of the genetic and other 
forms of CSI necessary to produce novel 
organismal form? If not, as this review has 
argued, could the emergence of novel in- 
formation-rich genes, proteins, cell types 
and body plans have resulted from actual 
design, rather than a purposeless process 
that merely mimics the powers of a design- 
ing intelligence? The logic of neo-Darwin- 
ism, with its specific claim to have account- 
ed for the appearance of design, would it- 
self seem to open the door to this possibil- 
ity. Indeed, the historical formulation of 
Darwinism in dialectical opposition to the 
design hypothesis (Gillespie 1979), coupled 
with neo-Darwinism’s inability to account 
for many salient appearances of design in- 
cluding the emergence of form and infor- 
mation, would seem logically to re-open the 
possibility of actual (as opposed to appar- 
ent) design in the history of life. 

A second reason for considering design 
as an explanation for these phenomena fol- 
lows from the importance of explanatory 
power to scientific theory evaluation and 
from a consideration of the potential ex- 
planatory power of the design hypothesis. 
Studies in the methodology and philosophy 
of science have shown that many scientific 
theories, particularly in the historical sci- 
ences, are formulated and justified as infer- 
ences to the best explanation (Lipton 1991: 



232 



PROCEEDINGS OF THE BIOLOGICAL SOCIETY OF WASHINGTON 



32-88, Brush 1989:1124-1129, Sober 
2000:44). Historical scientists, in particular, 
assess or test competing hypotheses by 
evaluating which hypothesis would, if true, 
provide the best explanation for some set of 
relevant data (Meyer 1991, 2002; Cleland 
2001:987-989, 2002:474-496). 10 Those 



10 Theories in the historical sciences typically make 
claims about what happened in the past, or what hap- 
pened in the past to cause particular events to occur 
(Meyer 1991:57-72). For this reason, historical sci- 
entific theories are rarely tested by making predictions 
about what will occur under controlled laboratory con- 
ditions (Cleland 2001:987, 2002:474-496). Instead, 
such theories are usually tested by comparing their ex- 
planatory power against that of their competitors with 
respect to already known facts. Even in the case in 
which historical theories make claims about past caus- 
es they usually do so on the basis of pre-existing 
knowledge of cause and effect relationships. Neverthe- 
less, prediction may play a limited role in testing his- 
torical scientific theories since such theories may have 
implications as to what kind of evidence is likely to 
emerge in the future. For example, neo-Darwinism af- 
firms that new functional sections of the genome arise 
by trial and error process of mutation and subsequent 
selection. For this reason, historically many neo-Dar- 
winists expected or predicted that the large non-coding 
regions of the genome — so-called “junk DNA — would 
lack function altogether (Orgel & Crick 1 980). On this 
line of thinking, the non-functional sections of the ge- 
nome represent nature’s failed experiments that remain 
in the genome as a kind of artifact of the past activity 
of the mutation and selection process. Advocates of 
the design hypotheses on the other hand, would have 
predicted that non-coding regions of the genome might 
well reveal hidden functions, not only because design 
theorists do not think that new genetic information 
arises by a trial and error process of mutation and se- 
lection, but also because designed systems are often 
functionally polyvalent. Even so, as new studies reveal 
more about the functions performed by the non-coding 
regions of the genome (Gibbs 2003), the design hy- 
pothesis can no longer be said to make this claim in 
the form of a specifically future-oriented prediction. 
Instead, the design hypothesis might be said to gain 
confirmation or support from its ability to explain this 
now known evidence, albeit after the fact. Of course, 
neo-Darwinists might also amend their original pre- 
diction using various auxiliary hypotheses to explain 
away the presence of newly discovered functions in 
the non-coding regions of DNA. In both cases, consid- 
erations of ex post facto explanatory power re-emerge 
as central to assessing and testing competing historical 
theories. 



with greater explanatory power are typical- 
ly judged to be better, more probably true, 
theories. Darwin (1896:437) used this 
method of reasoning in defending his the- 
ory of universal common descent. More- 
over, contemporary studies on the method 
of “inference to the best explanation” have 
shown that determining which among a set 
of competing possible explanations consti- 
tutes the best depends upon judgments 
about the causal adequacy, or “causal pow- 
ers,” of competing explanatory entities 
(Lipton 1991:32-88). In the historical sci- 
ences, uniformitarian and/or actualistic 
(Gould 1965, Simpson 1970, Rutten 1971, 
Hooykaas 1975) canons of method suggest 
that judgments about causal adequacy 
should derive from our present knowledge 
of cause and effect relationships. For his- 
torical scientists, “the present is the key to 
the past” means that present experience- 
based knowledge of cause and effect rela- 
tionships typically guides the assessment of 
the plausibility of proposed causes of past 
events. 

Yet it is precisely for this reason that cur- 
rent advocates of the design hypothesis 
want to reconsider design as an explanation 
for the origin of biological form and infor- 
mation. This review, and much of the lit- 
erature it has surveyed, suggests that four 
of the most prominent models for explain- 
ing the origin of biological form fail to pro- 
vide adequate causal explanations for the 
discontinuous increases of CSI that are re- 
quired to produce novel morphologies. Yet, 
we have repeated experience of rational and 
conscious agents — in particular ourselves — 
generating or causing increases in complex 
specified information, both in the form of 
sequence-specific lines of code and in the 
form of hierarchically arranged systems of 
parts. 

In the first place, intelligent human 
agents — in virtue of their rationality and 
consciousness — have demonstrated the 
power to produce information in the form 
of linear sequence-specific arrangements of 
characters. Indeed, experience affirms that 



VOLUME 117, NUMBER 2 



233 



information of this type routinely arises 
from the activity of intelligent agents. A 
computer user who traces the information 
on a screen back to its source invariably 
comes to a mind — that of a software engi- 
neer or programmer. The information in a 
book or inscription ultimately derives from 
a writer or scribe — from a mental, rather 
than a strictly material, cause. Our experi- 
ence-based knowledge of information-flow 
confirms that systems with large amounts of 
specified complexity (especially codes and 
languages) invariably originate from an in- 
telligent source — from a mind or personal 
agent. As Quastler (1964) put it, the “cre- 
ation of new information is habitually as- 
sociated with conscious activity” (p. 16). 
Experience teaches this obvious truth. 

Further, the highly specified hierarchical 
arrangements of parts in animal body plans 
also suggest design, again because of our 
experience of the kinds of features and sys- 
tems that designers can and do produce. At 
every level of the biological hierarchy, or- 
ganisms require specified and highly im- 
probable arrangements of lower-level con- 
stituents in order to maintain their form and 
function. Genes require specified arrange- 
ments of nucleotide bases; proteins require 
specified arrangements of amino acids; new 
cell types require specified arrangements of 
systems of proteins; body plans require spe- 
cialized arrangements of cell types and or- 
gans. Organisms not only contain informa- 
tion-rich components (such as proteins and 
genes), but they comprise information-rich 
arrangements of those components and the 
systems that comprise them. Yet we know, 
based on our present experience of cause 
and effect relationships, that design engi- 
neers — possessing purposive intelligence 
and rationality — have the ability to produce 
information-rich hierarchies in which both 
individual modules and the arrangements of 
those modules exhibit complexity and spec- 
ificity — information so defined. Individual 
transistors, resistors, and capacitors exhibit 
considerable complexity and specificity of 
design; at a higher level of organization. 



their specific arrangement within an inte- 
grated circuit represents additional infor- 
mation and reflects further design. Con- 
scious and rational agents have, as part of 
their powers of purposive intelligence, the 
capacity to design information-rich parts 
and to organize those parts into functional 
information-rich systems and hierarchies. 
Further, we know of no other causal entity 
or process that has this capacity. Clearly, 
we have good reason to doubt that mutation 
and selection, self-organizational processes 
or laws of nature, can produce the infor- 
mation-rich components, systems, and body 
plans necessary to explain the origination 
of morphological novelty such as that 
which arises in the Cambrian period. 

There is a third reason to consider pur- 
pose or design as an explanation for the or- 
igin of biological form and information: 
purposive agents have just those necessary 
powers that natural selection lacks as a con- 
dition of its causal adequacy. At several 
points in the previous analysis, we saw that 
natural selection lacked the ability to gen- 
erate novel information precisely because it 
can only act after new functional CSI has 
arisen. Natural selection can favor new pro- 
teins, and genes, but only after they per- 
form some function. The job of generating 
new functional genes, proteins and systems 
of proteins therefore falls entirely to ran- 
dom mutations. Yet without functional cri- 
teria to guide a search through the space of 
possible sequences, random variation is 
probabilistically doomed. What is needed is 
not just a source of variation (i.e., the free- 
dom to search a space of possibilities) or a 
mode of selection that can operate after the 
fact of a successful search, but instead a 
means of selection that (a) operates during 
a search — before success — and that (b) is 
guided by information about, or knowledge 
of, a functional target. 

Demonstration of this requirement has 
come from an unlikely quarter: genetic al- 
gorithms. Genetic algorithms are programs 
that allegedly simulate the creative power 
of mutation and selection. Dawkins and 



234 



PROCEEDINGS OF THE BIOLOGICAL SOCIETY OF WASHINGTON 



Kuppers, for example, have developed 
computer programs that putatively simulate 
the production of genetic information by 
mutation and natural selection (Dawkins 
1986:47-49, Kuppers 1987:355-369). Nev- 
ertheless, as shown elsewhere (Meyer 1998: 
127-128, 2003:247-248), these programs 
only succeed by the illicit expedient of pro- 
viding the computer with a “target se- 
quence” and then treating relatively greater 
proximity to future function (i.e., the target 
sequence), not actual present function, as a 
selection criterion. As Berlinski (2000) has 
argued, genetic algorithms need something 
akin to a “forward looking memory” in or- 
der to succeed. Yet such foresighted selec- 
tion has no analogue in nature. In biology, 
where differential survival depends upon 
maintaining function, selection cannot oc- 
cur before new functional sequences arise. 
Natural selection lacks foresight. 

What natural selection lacks, intelligent 
selection — purposive or goal-directed de- 
sign — provides. Rational agents can arrange 
both matter and symbols with distant goals 
in mind. In using language, the human 
mind routinely “finds” or generates highly 
improbable linguistic sequences to convey 
an intended or preconceived idea. In the 
process of thought, functional objectives 
precede and constrain the selection of 
words, sounds and symbols to generate 
functional (and indeed meaningful) se- 
quences from among a vast ensemble of 
meaningless alternative combinations of 
sound or symbol (Denton 1986:309-311). 
Similarly, the construction of complex tech- 
nological objects and products, such as 
bridges, circuit boards, engines and soft- 
ware, result from the application of goal- 
directed constraints (Polanyi 1967, 1968). 
Indeed, in all functionally integrated com- 
plex systems where the cause is known by 
experience or observation, design engineers 
or other intelligent agents applied boundary 
constraints to limit possibilities in order to 
produce improbable forms, sequences or 
structures. Rational agents have repeatedly 
demonstrated the capacity to constrain the 



possible to actualize improbable but initial- 
ly unrealized future functions. Repeated ex- 
perience affirms that intelligent agents 
(minds) uniquely possess such causal pow- 
ers. 

Analysis of the problem of the origin of 
biological information, therefore, exposes a 
deficiency in the causal powers of natural 
selection that corresponds precisely to pow- 
ers that agents are uniquely known to pos- 
sess. Intelligent agents have foresight. Such 
agents can select functional goals before 
they exist. They can devise or select mate- 
rial means to accomplish those ends from 
among an array of possibilities and then ac- 
tualize those goals in accord with a pre con- 
ceived design plan or set of functional re- 
quirements. Rational agents can constrain 
combinatorial space with distant outcomes 
in mind. The causal powers that natural se- 
lection lacks — almost by definition — are as- 
sociated with the attributes of conscious- 
ness and rationality — with purposive intel- 
ligence. Thus, by invoking design to ex- 
plain the origin of new biological 
information, contemporary design theorists 
are not positing an arbitrary explanatory el- 
ement unmotivated by a consideration of 
the evidence. Instead, they are positing an 
entity possessing precisely the attributes 
and causal powers that the phenomenon in 
question requires as a condition of its pro- 
duction and explanation. 

Conclusion 

An experience-based analysis of the 
causal powers of various explanatory hy- 
potheses suggests purposive or intelligent 
design as a causally adequate — and perhaps 
the most causally adequate — explanation 
for the origin of the complex specified in- 
formation required to build the Cambrian 
animals and the novel forms they represent. 
For this reason, recent scientific interest in 
the design hypothesis is unlikely to abate as 
biologists continue to wrestle with the prob- 
lem of the origination of biological form 
and the higher taxa. 



VOLUME 1 17, NUMBER 2 



235 



Literature Cited 

Adams, M. D. et alia. 2000. The genome sequence of 
Drosophila melanogaster . — Science 287:2185- 
2195. 

Aris-Brosou, S., & Z. Yang. 2003. Bayesian models of 
episodic evolution support a late Precambrian 
explosive diversification of the Metazoa. — Mo- 
lecular Biology and Evolution 20:1947-1954. 

Arthur, W. 1997. The origin of animal body plans. 
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, Unit- 
ed Kingdom. 

Axe, D. D. 2000. Extreme functional sensitivity to 
conservative amino acid changes on enzyme ex- 
teriors. — Journal of Molecular Biology 301(3): 
585-596. 

. 2004. Estimating the prevalence of protein se- 
quences adopting functional enzyme folds. — 
Journal of Molecular Biology (in press). 

Ayala, E 1994. Darwin’s revolution. Pp. 1-17 in J. 
Campbell and J. Schopf, eds., Creative evolu- 
tion?! Jones and 'Bartlett Publishers, Boston, 
Massachusetts. 

, A. Rzhetsky, & F. J. Ayala. 1998. Origin of 

the metazoan phyla: molecular clocks confirm 
paleontological estimates. — Proceedings of the 
National Academy of Sciences USA. 95:606- 
611. 

Becker, H., & W. Lonnig. 2001. Transposons: eukary- 
otic. Pp. 529-539 in Nature encyclopedia of life 
sciences, vol. 18. Nature Publishing Group, 
London, United Kingdom. 

Behe, M. 1992. Experimental support for regarding 
functional classes of proteins to be highly iso- 
lated from each other. Pp. 60-71 in J. Buell and 
V. Hearn, eds., Darwinism: science or philoso- 
phy? Foundation for Thought and Ethics, Rich- 
ardson, Texas. 

. 1996. Darwin’s black box. The Free Press, 

New York. 

. 2004. Irreducible complexity: obstacle to Dar- 
winian evolution. Pp. 352-370 in W. A. Demb- 
ski and M. Ruse, eds.. Debating design: from 
Darwin to DNA. Cambridge University Press, 
Cambridge, United Kingdom. 

Benton, M., & F. J. Ayala. 2003. Dating the tree of 
life.— Science 300:1698-1700. 

Berlinski, D. 2000. “On assessing genetic algorithms.” 
Public lecture. Conference: Science and evi- 
dence of design in the universe. Yale Univer- 
sity, November 4, 2000. 

Blanco, E, I. Angrand, & L. Serrano. 1999. Exploring 
the confirmational properties of the sequence 
space between two proteins with different folds: 
an experimental study. — Journal of Molecular 
Biology 285: 741-753. 

Bowie, J., & R. Sauer. 1989. Identifying determinants 
of folding and activity for a protein of unknown 



sequences: tolerance to amino acid substitu- 
tion. — Proceedings of the National Academy of 
Sciences, U.S.A. 86:2152-2156. 

Bowring, S. A., J. P. Grotzinger, C. E. Isachsen, A. H. 
Knoll, S. M. Pelechaty, & P. Kolosov. 1993. 
Calibrating rates of early Cambrian evolu- 
tion. — Science 261:1293-1298. 

. 1998a. A new look at evolutionary rates in 

deep time: Uniting paleontology and high-pre- 
cision geochronology. — GSA Today 8:1-8. 

. 1998b. Geochronology comes of age. — Geo- 
times 43:36-40. 

Bradley, W. 2004. Information, entropy and the origin 
of life. Pp. 331-351 in W. A. Dembski and M. 
Ruse, eds.. Debating design: from Darwin to 
DNA. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 
United Kingdom. 

Brocks, J. J., G. A. Logan, R. Buick, & R. E. Sum- 
mons. 1999. Archean molecular fossils and the 
early rise of eukaryotes. — Science 285:1033- 
1036. 

Brush, S. G. 1989. Prediction and theory evaluation: 
the case of light bending. — Science 246:1124- 
1129. 

Budd, G. E., & S. E. Jensen. 2000. A critical reap- 
praisal of the fossil record of the bilaterial phy- 
la. — Biological Reviews of the Cambridge Phil- 
osophical Society 75:253-295. 

Carroll, R. L. 2000. Towards a new evolutionary syn- 
thesis. — Trends in Ecology and Evolution 15: 
27-32. 

Cleland, C. 2001. Historical science, experimental sci- 
ence, and the scientific method. — Geology 29: 
987-990. 

. 2002. Methodological and epistemic differ- 
ences between historical science and experi- 
mental science. — Philosophy of Science 69: 
474-496. 

Chothia, C., I. Gelfland, & A. Kister. 1998. Structural 
determinants in the sequences of immunoglob- 
ulin variable domain. — Journal of Molecular 
Biology 278:457-479. 

Conway Morris, S. 1998a. The question of metazoan 
monophyly and the fossil record. — Progress in 
Molecular and Subcellular Biology 21:1-9. 

. 1998b. Early Metazoan evolution: reconciling 

paleontology and molecular biology. — Ameri- 
can Zoologist 38 (1998):867-877. 

. 2000. Evolution: bringing molecules into the 

fold.— Cell 100:1-11. 

. 2003a. The Cambrian “explosion” of meta- 
zoans. Pp. 13-32 in G. B. Muller and S. A. 
Newman, eds., Origination of organismal form: 
beyond the gene in developmental and evolu- 
tionary biology. The M.I.T. Press, Cambridge, 
Massachusetts. 

. 2003b. Cambrian “explosion” of metazoans 

and molecular biology: would Darwin be sat- 



236 



PROCEEDINGS OF THE BIOLOGICAL SOCIETY OF WASHINGTON 



isfied? — International Journal of Developmental 
Biology 47(7-8):505-515. 

. 2003c. Life’s solution: inevitable humans in a 

lonely universe. Cambridge University Press, 
Cambridge, United Kingdom. 

Crick, F. 1958. On protein synthesis. — Symposium for 
the Society of Experimental Biology. 12(1958): 
138-163. 

Darwin, C. 1859. On the origin of species. John Mur- 
ray, London, United Kingdom. 

. 1896. Letter to Asa Gray. P. 437 in F. Darwin, 

ed.. Life and letters of Charles Darwin, vol. 1. 
D. Appleton, London, United Kingdom. 

Davidson, E. 2001. Genomic regulatory systems: de- 
velopment and evolution. Academic Press, New 
York, New York. 

Dawkins, R. 1986. The blind watchmaker. Penguin 
Books, London, United Kingdom. 

. 1995. River out of Eden. Basic Books, New 

York. 

. 1996. Climbing Mount Improbable. W. W. 

Norton & Company, New York. 

Dembksi, W. A. 1998. The design inference. Cam- 
bridge University Press, Cambridge, United 
Kingdom. 

. 2002. No free lunch: why specified complex- 
ity cannot be purchased without intelligence. 
Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, Maryland. 

. 2004. The logical underpinnings of intelligent 

design. Pp. 311-330 in W. A. Dembski and M. 
Ruse, eds.. Debating design: from Darwin to 
DNA. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 
United Kingdom. 

Denton, M. 1986. Evolution: a theory in crisis. Adler 
& Adler, London, United Kingdom. 

. 1998. Nature’s destiny. The Free Press, New 

York. 

Eden, M. 1967. The inadequacies of neo-Darwinian 
evolution as a scientific theory. Pp. 5—12 in P. 
S. Morehead and M. M. Kaplan, eds.. Mathe- 
matical challenges to the Darwinian interpreta- 
tion of evolution. Wistar Institute Symposium 
Monograph. Allen R. Liss, New York. 

Eldredge, N., & S. J. Gould. 1972. Punctuated equilib- 
ria: an alternative to phyletic gradualism. Pp. 
82-1 15 in T. Schopf, ed.. Models in paleobiol- 
ogy. W. H. Freeman, San Francisco. 

Erwin, D. H. 1994. Early introduction of major mor- 
phological innovations. — Acta Palaeontologica 
Polonica 38:281-294. 

. 2000. Macroevolution is more than repeated 

rounds of microevolution. — Evolution & De- 
velopment 2:78-84. 

. 2004. One very long argument. — Biology and 

Philosophy 19:17-28. 

, J. Valentine, & D. Jablonski. 1997. The origin 

of animal body plans. — American Scientist 85: 
126-137. 



, , & J. J. Sepkoski. 1987. A compara- 
tive study of diversification events: the early Pa- 
leozoic versus the Mesozoic. — Evolution 41: 
1177-1186. 

Foote, M. 1997. Sampling, taxonomic description, and 
our evolving knowledge of morphological di- 
versity. — Paleobiology 23:1 81-206. 

, J. P. Hunter, C. M. Janis, & J. J. Sepkoski. 

1999. Evolutionary and preservational con- 
straints on origins of biologic groups: Diver- 
gence times of eutherian mammals. — Science 
283:1310-1314. 

Frankel, J. 1 980. Propagation of cortical differences in 
tetrahymena. — Genetics 94:607-623. 

Gates, B. 1996. The road ahead. Blue Penguin, Boul- 
der, Colorado. 

Gerhart, J., & M. Kirschner. 1997. Cells, embryos, and 
evolution. Blackwell Science, London, United 
Kingdom. 

Gibbs, W. W. 2003. The unseen genome: gems among 
the junk. — Scientific American. 289:46-53 

Gilbert, S. F., J. M. Opitz, & R. A. Raff. 1996. Resyn- 
thesizing evolutionary and developmental biol- 
ogy. — Developmental Biology 173:357-372. 

Gillespie, N. C. 1979. Charles Darwin and the problem 
of creation. University of Chicago Press, Chi- 
cago. 

Goodwin, B. C. 1985. What are the causes of mor- 
phogenesis? — BioEssays 3:32-36. 

. 1995. How the leopard changed its spots: the 

evolution of complexity. Scribner’s, New York, 
New York. 

Gould, S. J. 1965. Is uniformitarianism necessary? — 
American Journal of Science 263:223-228. 

Gould, S. J. 2002. The structure of evolutionary the- 
ory. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 
Massachusetts. 

Grant, P. R. 1999. Ecology and evolution of Darwin’s 
finches. Princeton University Press, Princeton, 
New Jersey. 

Grimes, G. W„ & K. J. Aufderheide. 1991. Cellular 
aspects of pattern formation: the problem of as- 
sembly. Monographs in Developmental Biolo- 
gy, vol. 22. Karger, Basel, Switzerland. 

Grotzinger, J. P„ S. A. Bowring, B. Z. Saylor, & A. J. 
Kaufman. 1995. Biostratigraphic and geochro- 
nologic constraints on early animal evolution. — 
Science 270:598-604. 

Harold, F. M. 1995. From morphogenes to morpho- 
genesis. — Microbiology 141:2765-2778. 

. 2001. The way of the cell: molecules, organ- 
isms, and the order of life. Oxford University 
Press, New York. 

Hodge, M. J. S. 1977. The structure and strategy of 
Darwin’s long argument. — British Journal for 
the History of Science 10:237-245. 

Hooykaas, R. 1975. Catastrophism in geology, its sci- 
entific character in relation to actualism and 



VOLUME 117, NUMBER 2 



237 



uniformitarianism. Pp. 270-316 in C. Albritton, 
ed„ Philosophy of geohistory (1785-1970). 
Dowden, Hutchinson & Ross, Stroudsburg, 
Pennsylvania. 

John, B., & G. Miklos. 1988. The eukaryote genome 
in development and evolution. Allen & Unwin, 
London, United Kingdom. 

Kauffman, S. 1995. At home in the universe. Oxford 
University Press, Oxford, United Kingdom. 

Kenyon, D., & G. Mills. 1996. The RNA world: a 
critique. — Origins & Design 17(1):9— 16. 

Kerr, R. A. 1993. Evolution’s Big Bang gets even more 
explosive. — Science 26 1 : 1 274-1 275 . 

Kimura, M. 1983. The neutral theory of molecular 
evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cam- 
bridge, United Kingdom. 

Koonin, E. 2000. How many genes can make a cell?: 
the minimal genome concept. — Annual Review 
of Genomics and Human Genetics 1:99—116. 

Kiippers, B. O. 1987. On the prior probability of the 
existence of life. Pp. 355-369 in L. Kruger et 
al., eds.. The probabilistic revolution. M.I.T. 
Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. 

Lange, B. M. H., A. J. Faragher, P. March, & K. Gull. 
2000. Centriole duplication and maturation in 
animal cells. Pp. 235-249 in R. E. Palazzo and 
G. P. Schatten, eds., The centrosome in cell rep- 
lication and early development. Current Topics 
in Developmental Biology, vol. 49. Academic 
Press, San Diego. 

Lawrence, P. A., & G. Struhl. 1996. Morphogens, com- 
partments and pattern: lessons from Drosophi- 
la?— Cell 85:951-961. 

Lenior, T. 1982. The strategy of life. University of Chi- 
cago Press, Chicago. 

Levinton, J. 1988. Genetics, paleontology, and mac- 
roevolution. Cambridge University Press, Cam- 
bridge, United Kingdom. 

. 1992. The big bang of animal evolution. — 

Scientific American 267:84-91. 

Lewin, R. 1988. A lopsided look at evolution. — Sci- 
ence 241:292. 

Lewontin, R. 1978. Adaptation. Pp. 113-125 in Evo- 
lution: a Scientific American book. W. H. Free- 
man & Company, San Francisco. 

Lipton, P. 1991. Inference to the best explanation. Rou- 
tledge. New York. 

Lonnig, W. E. 2001. Natural selection. Pp. 1008-1016 
in W. E. Craighead and C. B. Nemeroff, eds.. 
The Corsini encyclopedia of psychology and 
behavioral sciences, 3rd edition, vol. 3. John 
Wiley & Sons, New York. 

, & H. Saedler. 2002. Chromosome rearrange- 
ments and transposable elements. — Annual Re- 
view of Genetics 36:389-410. 

Lpvtrup, S. 1979. Semantics, logic and vulgate neo- 
darwinism.-Evolutionary Theory 4: 157-172. 

Marshall, W. E, & J. L. Rosenbaum. 2000. Are there 



nucleic acids in the centrosome? Pp. 187-205 
in R. E. Palazzo and G. P. Schatten, eds.. The 
centrosome in cell replication and early devel- 
opment. Current Topics in Developmental Bi- 
ology, vol. 49. San Diego, Academic Press. 

Maynard Smith, J. 1986. Structuralism versus selec- 
tion — is Darwinism enough? Pp. 39-46 in S. 
Rose and L. Appignanesi, eds.. Science and be- 
yond. Basil Blackwell, London, United King- 
dom. 

Mayr, E. 1982. Foreword. Pp. xi-xii in M. Ruse, Dar- 
winism defended. Pearson Addison Wesley, 
Boston, Massachusetts. 

McDonald, J. F. 1983. The molecular basis of adap- 
tation: a critical review of relevant ideas and 
observations. — Annual Review of Ecology and 
Systematics 14:77-102. 

McNiven, M. A., & K. R. Porter. 1992. The centro- 
some: contributions to cell form. Pp. 313-329 
in V. I. Kalnins, ed.. The centrosome. Academic 
Press, San Diego. 

Meyer, S. C. 1991. Of clues and causes: a methodo- 
logical interpretation of origin of life studies. 
Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of 
Cambridge, Cambridge, United Kingdom. 

. 1998. DNA by design: an inference to the best 

explanation for the origin of biological infor- 
mation. — Rhetoric & Public Affairs, 1(4):519- 
555. 

. The scientific status of intelligent design: The 

methodological equivalence of naturalistic and 
non-naturalistic origins theories. Pp. 151-211 in 
Science and evidence for design in the universe. 
Proceedings of the Wethersfield Institute. Igna- 
tius Press, San Francisco. 

. 2003. DNA and the origin of life: information, 

specification and explanation. Pp. 223-285 in J. 
A. Campbell and S. C. Meyer, eds., Darwinism, 
design and public education. Michigan State 
University Press, Lansing, Michigan. 

. 2004. The Cambrian information explosion: 

evidence for intelligent design. Pp. 371-391 in 
W. A. Dembski and M. Ruse, eds.. Debating 
design: from Darwin to DNA. Cambridge Uni- 
versity Press, Cambridge, United Kingdom. 

, M. Ross, P. Nelson, & P. Chien. 2003. The 

Cambrian explosion: biology’s big bang. Pp. 
323-402 in J. A. Campbell & S. C. Meyer, eds., 
Darwinism, design and public education. Mich- 
igan State University Press, Lansing. See also 
Appendix C: Stratigraphic first appearance of 
phyla body plans, pp. 593-598. 

Miklos, G. L. G. 1993. Emergence of organizational 
complexities during metazoan evolution: per- 
spectives from molecular biology, palaeontolo- 
gy and neo-Darwinism. — Mem. Ass. Australas. 
Palaeontols, 15:7-41. 



238 



PROCEEDINGS OF THE BIOLOGICAL SOCIETY OF WASHINGTON 



Monastersky, R. 1993. Siberian rocks clock biological 
big bang. — Science News 144:148. 

Moss, L. 2004. What genes can’t do. The M.I.T. Press, 
Cambridge, Massachusetts. 

Muller, G. B. & S. A. Newman. 2003. Origination of 
organismal form: the forgotten cause in evolu- 
tionary theory. Pp. 3-12 in G. B. Muller and S. 
A. Newman, eds.. Origination of organismal 
form: beyond the gene in developmental and 
evolutionary biology. The M.I.T. Press, Cam- 
bridge, Massachusetts. 

Nanney, D. L. 1983. The ciliates and the cytoplasm. — 
Journal of Heredity, 74:163-170. 

Nelson, P., & J. Wells. 2003. Homology in biology: 
problem for naturalistic science and prospect for 
intelligent design. Pp. 303-322 in J. A. Camp- 
bell and S. C. Meyer, eds., Darwinism, design 
and public education. Michigan State University 
Press, Lansing. 

Nijhout, H. F. 1990. Metaphors and the role of genes 
in development. — BioEssays 12:441-446. 

Nusslein-Volhard, C., & E. Wieschaus. 1980. Muta- 
tions affecting segment number and polarity in 
Drosophila. — Nature 287:795-801. 

Ohno, S. 1996. The notion of the Cambrian panani- 
malia genome. — Proceedings of the National 
Academy of Sciences, U.S.A. 93:8475-8478. 

Orgel, L. E„ & F. H. Crick. 1980. Selfish DNA: the 
ultimate parasite. — Nature 284:604-607. 

Perutz, M. F., & H. Lehmann. 1968. Molecular pa- 
thology of human hemoglobin. — Nature 219: 
902-909. 

Polanyi, M. 1967. Life transcending physics and 
chemistry. — Chemical and Engineering News, 
45(35):54-66. 

. 1968. Life’s irreducible structure. — Science 

160:1308-1312, especially p. 1309. 

Pourquie, O. 2003. Vertebrate somitogenesis: a novel 
paradigm for animal segmentation? — Interna- 
tional Journal of Developmental Biology 47(7- 
8):597-603. 

Quastler, H. 1964. The emergence of biological orga- 
nization. Yale University Press, New Haven, 
Connecticut. 

Raff, R. 1999. Larval homologies and radical evolu- 
tionary changes in early development, Pp. 1 10- 
121 in Homology. Novartis Symposium, vol. 
222. John Wiley & Sons, Chichester, United 
Kingdom. 

Reidhaar-Olson, J., & R. Sauer. 1990. Functionally ac- 
ceptable solutions in two alpha-helical regions 
of lambda repressor. — Proteins, Structure, Func- 
tion, and Genetics, 7:306-316. 

Rutten, M. G. 1971. The origin of life by natural caus- 
es. Elsevier, Amsterdam. 

Sapp, J. 1987. Beyond the gene. Oxford University 
Press, New York. 

Sarkar, S. 1996. Biological information: a skeptical 



look at some central dogmas of molecular bi- 
ology. Pp. 187—233 in S. Sarkar, ed.. The phi- 
losophy and history of molecular biology: new 
perspectives. Kluwer Academic Publishers, 
Dordrecht. 

Schiitzenberger, M. 1967. Algorithms and the neo-Dar- 
winian theory of evolution. Pp. 73-75 in P. S. 
Morehead and M. M. Kaplan, eds.. Mathemat- 
ical challenges to the Darwinian interpretation 
of evolution. Wistar Institute Symposium 
Monograph. Allen R. Liss, New York. 

Shannon, C. 1948. A mathematical theory of com- 
munication. — Bell System Technical Journal 
27:379-423, 623-656. 

Shu, D. G., H. L. Lou, S. Conway Morris, X. L. Zhang, 
S. X. Hu, L. Chen, J. Han, M. Zhu, Y. Li, & L. 
Z. Chen. 1999. Lower Cambrian vertebrates 
from south China. — Nature 402:42-46. 

Shubin, N. H., & C. R. Marshall. 2000. Fossils, genes, 
and the origin of novelty. Pp. 324-340 in Deep 
time. The Paleontological Society. 

Simpson, G. 1970. Uniformitarianism: an inquiry into 
principle, theory, and method in geohistory and 
biohistory. Pp. 43-96 in M. K. Hecht and W. 
C. Steere, eds., Essays in evolution and genetics 
in honor of Theodosius Dobzhansky. Appleton- 
Century-Crofts, New York. 

Sober, E. 2000. The philosophy of biology, 2nd edi- 
tion. Westview Press, San Francisco. 

Sonneborn, T. M. 1970. Determination, development, 
and inheritance of the structure of the cell cor- 
tex. In Symposia of the International Society for 
Cell Biology 9:1-13. 

Sole, R. V., P. Fernandez, & S. A. Kauffman. 2003. 
Adaptive walks in a gene network model of 
morphogenesis: insight into the Cambrian ex- 
plosion. — International Journal of Developmen- 
tal Biology 47(7-8):685-693. 

Stadler, B. M. R„ P. F. Stadler, G. P. Wagner, & W. 
Fontana. 2001. The topology of the possible: 
formal spaces underlying patterns of evolution- 
ary change. — Journal of Theoretical Biology 
213:241-274. 

Steiner, M„ & R. Reitner. 2001. Evidence of organic 
structures in Ediacara-type fossils and associ- 
ated microbial mats. — Geology 29(12):! 1 19 — 
1122. 

Taylor, S. V., K. U. Walter, P. Kast, & D. Hilvert. 2001. 
Searching sequence space for protein cata- 
lysts. — Proceedings of the National Academy of 
Sciences, U.S.A. 98:10596-10601. 

Thaxton, C. B„ W. L. Bradley, & R. L. Olsen. 1992. 
The mystery of life’s origin: reassessing current 
theories. Lewis and Stanley, Dallas, Texas. 

Thompson, D. W. 1942. On growth and form, 2nd edi- 
tion. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 
United Kingdom. 

Thomson, K. S. 1992. Macroevolution: The morpho- 



VOLUME 1 17, NUMBER 2 



239 



logical problem. — American Zoologist 32:106— 

112 . 

Valentine, J. W. 1995. Late Precambrian bilaterians: 
grades and clades. Pp. 87-107 in W. M. Fitch 
and F.J. Ayala, eds.. Tempo and mode in evo- 
lution: genetics and paleontology 50 years after 
Simpson. National Academy Press, Washington, 
D.C. 

. 2004. On the origin of phyla. University of 

Chicago Press, Chicago, Illinois. 

, & D. H. Erwin. 1987. Interpreting great de- 
velopmental experiments: the fossil record. Pp. 
71-107 in R. A. Raff and E. C. Raff, eds., De- 
velopment as an evolutionary process. Alan R. 
Liss, New York. 

, & D. Jablonski. 2003. Morphological and de- 
velopmental macroevolution: a paleontological 
perspective. — International Journal of Devel- 
opmental Biology 47:517-522. 

Wagner, G. P. 2001. What is the promise of develop- 
mental evolution? Part II: A causal explanation 
of evolutionary innovations may be impossi- 
ble. — Journal of Experimental Zoology (Mol. 
Dev. Evol.) 291:305-309. 

, & P. F. Stadler. 2003. Quasi-independence, ho- 
mology and the unity of type: a topological the- 
ory of characters. — Journal of Theoretical Bi- 
ology 220:505-527. 

Webster, G., & B. Goodwin. 1984. A structuralist ap- 



proach to morphology. — Ri vista di Biologia 77: 
503-10. 

, & . 1996. Form and transformation: 

generative and relational principles in biology. 
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, Unit- 
ed Kingdom. 

Weiner, J. 1 994. The beak of the finch. Vintage Books, 
New York. 

Willmer, P. 1990. Invertebrate relationships: patterns in 
animal evolution. Cambridge University Press, 
Cambridge, United Kingdom. 

. 2003. Convergence and homoplasy in the 

evolution of organismal form. Pp. 33-50 in G. 
B. Muller and S. A. Newman, eds., Origination 
of organismal form: beyond the gene in devel- 
opmental and evolutionary biology. The M.I.T. 
Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. 

Woese, C. 1998. The universal ancestor. — Proceedings 
of the National Academy of Sciences, U.S.A. 
95:6854-6859. 

Wray, G. A., J. S. Levinton, & L. H. Shapiro. 1996. 
Molecular evidence for deep Precambrian di- 
vergences among metazoan phyla. — Science 
274:568-573. 

Yockey, H. P. 1978. A calculation of the probability of 
spontaneous biogenesis by information theo- 
ry. — Journal of Theoretical Biology 67:377- 
398. 

. 1992. Information theory and molecular bi- 
ology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 
United Kingdom.